




Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Prepare for your exams
Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points to download
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Community
Ask the community for help and clear up your study doubts
Discover the best universities in your country according to Docsity users
Free resources
Download our free guides on studying techniques, anxiety management strategies, and thesis advice from Docsity tutors
This study investigates how essentialist thinking about race influences children's memory for racially ambiguous faces. The researchers found that White children who used essentialist thinking remembered White faces significantly better than ambiguous and Black faces, while children who did not use essentialist thinking remembered both White and ambiguous faces better than Black faces. This suggests that essentialist thinking can lead to more distinct racial boundaries and poorer memory for racially ambiguous individuals.
Typology: Summaries
1 / 8
This page cannot be seen from the preview
Don't miss anything!
BRIEF REPORT
Essentialist Thinking Predicts Decrements in Children’s Memory for
Racially Ambiguous Faces
Tufts University
University of Hawaii
Tufts University
Stanford University
Past research shows that adults often display poor memory for racially ambiguous and racial outgroup faces, with both face types remembered worse than own-race faces. In the present study, the authors examined whether children also show this pattern of results. They also examined whether emerging essentialist thinking about race predicts children’s memory for faces. Seventy-four White children (ages 4 –9 years) completed a face-memory task comprising White, Black, and racially ambiguous Black– White faces. Essentialist thinking about race was also assessed (i.e., thinking of race as immutable and biologically based). White children who used essentialist thinking showed the same bias as White adults: They remembered White faces significantly better than they remembered ambiguous and Black faces. However, children who did not use essentialist thinking remembered both White and racially ambiguous faces significantly better than they remembered Black faces. This finding suggests a specific shift in racial thinking wherein the boundaries between racial groups become more discrete, highlighting the importance of how race is conceptualized in judgments of racially ambiguous individuals.
Keywords: own-race bias, racially ambiguous, face memory, racial essentialism
Although race is a socially constructed category used to sort humans into distinct groups, people often treat this category as naturally existing (e.g., Markus, 2008). People frequently con- strue race as biologically based and immutable and ascribe inherent meaning to these categories on the basis of physical characteristics associated with racial groups (Rothbart & Tay- lor, 1992). In adults, such essentialist thinking about race has been shown to lead to prejudice and decreased motivation to
cross racial boundaries (e.g., Haslam, Rothschild, & Ernst, 2002; Jayaratne et al., 2006; Keller, 2005; Levy, Stroessner, & Dweck, 1998; Williams & Eberhardt, 2008; Yzerbyt, Rocher, & Schadron, 1997). However, only a handful of studies have explored the social consequences of essentialist thinking in children. Here, we examined whether children’s emerging es- sentialist thinking about race has consequences for their mem- ory for faces at the boundary of race (i.e., racially ambiguous faces). Essentialist thinking is grounded in the belief that certain cate- gories have important underlying essences that define their nature (Gelman, 2003; Medin & Ortony, 1989). Developmental work on psychological essentialism has demonstrated that children exhibit essentialist thinking about both biological animal categories (e.g., Gelman & Wellman, 1991) and a specific subset of social catego- ries (e.g., race and gender; Hirschfeld, 1995; Rhodes & Gelman, 2009; Taylor, 1996) as early as age 4 years. Essentialism has been defined in a variety of ways in the literature (see Gelman, 2003; Medin & Ortony, 1989, for reviews), but essentialist thinking about social categories is thought to possess two main compo- nents: inalterable membership and inductive potential (Rothbart & Taylor, 1992). Although there are many aspects of essentialism, here we focus on the implications of one component of essentialist thinking—the perception of the inalterability of group member- ship—within the domain of race. We examined several features that are consistently viewed as central to essentialist beliefs—that
Sarah E. Gaither and Jennifer R. Schultz, Department of Psychology, Tufts University; Kristin Pauker, Department of Psychology, University of Hawaii; Samuel R. Sommers and Keith B. Maddox, Department of Psy- chology, Tufts University; Nalini Ambady, Department of Psychology, Stanford University. We thank the Living Laboratory at the Museum of Science, Boston, Massachusetts; the Tufts Educational Day Care Center; the Eliot-Pearson Children’s School for recruitment assistance; and all of the families for participating. This work was supported by a National Science Foundation Graduate Research Fellowship and a Tufts Graduate Research Award, both awarded to Sarah E. Gaither; National Institute of Child Development Award K99HD065741-02 granted to Kristin Pauker; and a grant from the Russell Sage Foundation awarded to Samuel R. Sommers. Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Sarah E. Gaither, Department of Psychology, Tufts University, 490 Boston Avenue, Medford
1
ognition for White faces over both racially ambiguous and Black faces.
A total of 89 White children were recruited from two schools and a museum science center in the greater Boston area. Parents were informed about the study, including its focus on racial per- ceptions, either from a letter sent home by the school administra- tion (35% response rate) or through an in-person invitation to participate at the science center (80% response rate). We used an a priori exclusion criterion based on the idea that children who showed memory at chance levels across all face types during the memory task either were not paying attention or found the task was too difficult. Thus, data from 13 participants were excluded. Ad- ditionally, two other children were excluded who used a response pattern (i.e., alternating right face, left face) during the recognition phase. These exclusions resulted in a final sample of 74 White children (45 female) between the ages of 4 and 9 years ( M 5. years, SD 1.50). Children were recruited from two schools ( n
For participants recruited from schools, parents were asked to complete an optional demographic form that asked them to specify their child’s racial background. At the science center, parents were asked this question in person. After receiving parental consent, the experimenter asked for children’s verbal assent and made clear that they could stop the study at any point. Children completed the study on a computer that was separate from the classroom or separate from other children at the science center. Each participant completed two tasks: a face memory task and a racial essentialism assessment. To avoid carryover effects from tasks that were spe- cifically about race (e.g., racial essentialism), the memory task always came first to minimize suspicion about the hypothesis. Memory task. We used the face recognition procedure used in Pauker et al. (2009) on adults but with fewer faces to make it easier for children. Participants were told that they were going to play a memory game and that they would receive stickers in exchange for participating. The experimenter told the children to pay close attention to each face and explained that they would be asked to say which faces they had seen before. A subset of Pauker et al.’s (2009) computer-generated White, Black, and racially ambiguous (Black–White) adult faces was used as stimuli. All of the faces were previously pretested to ensure they were prototypical of White or Black faces or fell in between and were perceived as truly ambiguous. All of the faces depicted neutral facial expressions and were equated for attractiveness (see
Pauker et al., 2009). Faces varied with respect to both skin color and other features prototypically associated with White and Black faces (e.g., shape of lips). The task included two phases. During the learning phase, participants viewed four White faces, four Black faces, and four ambiguous Black–White faces (hereafter called target faces ). An equal number of male and female faces were included in each racial category. Each target face was ad- justed to uniform size and resolution (500 500 pixels; 3.5 3 in.; 153 pixels/in.) and was shown in a randomized order for 5, ms, followed by a fixation cross with an intertrial interval of 1, ms. After completing the learning phase, participants were asked a few distracter questions (e.g., “What are you doing this weekend?” “What have you seen at the museum so far?”). In the recognition phase, participants were shown the 12 target faces from the learn- ing phase in addition to 12 foil faces: four White, four Black, and four racially ambiguous, all of which were gender balanced. The foil faces were shown next to a target face of the same race and gender, and these pairings were displayed in a random order. During the recognition phase, children were instructed that they would see two faces, one on the right side and one on the left side of the screen, and that they should both point to the face that they had seen before and press the L key if the face was on the left and the R key if the face was on the right. These keys were clearly labeled with stickers to minimize confusion. No feedback on accuracy was provided. The dependent measure of interest was recognition memory (measured by d =). Racial essentialism. After the memory task, participants com- pleted a short three-item racial essentialism measure, adapted from previous tasks, that examined children’s beliefs about immutability of category membership (Hirschfeld, 1995; Ruble et al., 2007; Semaj, 1980). Participants were first shown three faces (all photos were matched to the child’s gender): One was either a Black or a White child whose photo was placed above that of a Black adult and a White adult. The experimenter asked, “When this child grows up, will they look more like this adult [White] or that adult [Black]?” (the order of the adult photos was counterbalanced across all participants). Next, participants viewed a similar picture array except they saw either a Black or a White adult pictured above a Black child and a White child (in counterbalanced order). The experimenter then asked, “When this adult was little, did they look more like this child [White] or that child [Black]?” Finally, the experimenter pointed to a picture of a White child and asked, “If this child really wanted to be Black and change his/her skin color could he/she do that?” To uncover their reasoning, the experimenter then asked children to explain why they believed that the child could or could not change his or her racial group mem- bership. Children were categorized as having essentialist thinking about race if they (a) correctly made a race match in the first two questions and answered “no” to the last question, indicating that they believe race is both stable across the lifespan and immutable, and (b) used essentialist reasoning in their explanation for why someone could not change their skin color by referencing either immutability (e.g., “black skin stays forever”), inheritability or biology (e.g., “you stay the same because you are born that way”), or naturalness (e.g., “can’t change his skin, he was made that way”; see Pauker, Ambady, & Apfelbaum, 2010, and Ruble et al., 2007, for similar methods and coding strategies). If children did not provide reasoning for their answer or if that reasoning did not
fall into any of the above categories (i.e., reasoning such as “they like being that way”), children were coded as non–racially essen- tialist. In other words, children needed to answer all questions correctly and provide essentialist reasoning to be coded as having racial essentialism. Hirschfeld (1995) argued that some work underestimates chil- dren’s understanding of race as an unchanging, biologically based category because it uses hard-to-understand tasks. To avoid such issues, we modeled our measure on those that examine natural changes over the lifespan (i.e., growth) with a couple of key additions. First, we used real pictures as our stimuli. Past research has mostly used drawings (e.g., Giménez & Harris, 2002; Hirschfeld, 1995), which may limit the generalizability of the findings (e.g., maybe children do not conceptualize drawings in the same way that they do actual people). Second, we probed for children’s self-produced reasoning about whether a change in racial group membership is possible and coded for explanations consistent with essentialist beliefs: that a category is stable, un- changing, likely to be present at birth, natural, and biologically based. Examining children’s social reasoning in this way provides valuable insight into children’s understandings of concepts not available through simple forced-choice measures (e.g., Giménez & Harris, 2002; Killen & Stangor, 2001; Taylor, Rhodes, & Gelman, 2009). This measure of racial essentialism has been used in past research and reliably relates to children’s racial stereotyping (Pauker et al., 2009). On the basis of this task, children were divided into two groups: nonessentialist and essentialist. After all the tasks were completed, children chose some stickers as a reward for participating.
We calculated d = scores using the proportion of correct choices from the face recognition task. Since this was a two-alternative forced choice (2AFC) paradigm, we used the following formula to calculate d =: z score [proportion correct] 2 (Macmillan & Creelman, 2005). When proportion correct is equal to 1 or 0, no z score can be calculated; therefore, we calculated corrected propor- tions that were based on the number of signal or noise trials ( n 4; Stanislaw & Todorov, 1999). When the proportion correct equaled 0, the value was recoded as 0.5/ n, and when the proportion correct equaled 1, the value was recoded as 1 (0.5/ n ). No differences were found relating to either participant gender or the gender of stimuli, so analyses were collapsed across these vari- ables.
To test our hypotheses, we compared memory for the target faces between children with essentialist reasoning ( n 35; 19 female) and those without essentialist reasoning ( n 39; 26 female). We ran a 3 (target race: White, Black, and ambiguous) 2 (racial essentialism: yes or no) mixed-model analysis of variance on the measure of face recognition memory: the mean d = scores. There was a significant interaction between target race and racial essentialism, F (2, 144) 3.76, p .03, ^2 .050, and a main effect only for target race, F (2, 144) 4.06, p .02, ^2 .
(see Figure 1). To further examine the differences in memory associated with essentialist thinking, planned contrasts were con- ducted on the d = scores for White, Black, and racially ambiguous faces for children with and without racial essentialist reasoning. As predicted (and similar to adults in prior research), children with essentialist beliefs remembered White faces ( M .96, SD .78) significantly better than they did both ambiguous ( M .30, SD .78) and Black faces ( M .49, SD 1.0), t (144) 3.05, p .002, r .25. In comparison, children without essentialist beliefs remembered both White ( M .63, SD .82) and ambiguous ( M .72, SD .64) faces better than they did Black faces ( M .28, SD 1.1), t (144) 2.25, p .02, r .18. Furthermore, children without essentialist beliefs recognized ambiguous faces significantly better than did children with essentialist beliefs, t (144) 2.01, p .03, r .17. We examined race essentialism and memory over a wide age range, under the assumption that we should find considerable variability in race essentialism in this age range, presumably with more essentialist reasoning occurring as children got older. We found only moderate support for this premise. Although there was variability in essentialist reasoning in this age range, there were no significant differences in the average age of children who exhib- ited ( M 6.13, SD 1.16) or did not exhibit ( M 5.80, SD 1.75) essentialist reasoning. On the basis of prior research that found 6-year-olds typically displayed essentialist reasoning (Pauker, Ambady, & Apfelbaum, 2010), we also compared use of essentialism in 4- to 5-year-olds and 6- to 9-year-olds. A greater proportion of older (6- to 9-year-old) children (60.5%) used es- sentialism compared with younger (4- to 5-year-old) children (29%), ^2 (1) 0.714, p .008. Together with the prior analysis, support for clear age differences in essentialist reasoning in our study is inconclusive at best. However, an additional analysis controlling for age as a variable did not change any of the above memory effects, nor did it interact with racial essentialism or target race of the stimuli.
This is the first study, to our knowledge, to relate essentialist thinking about race to memory for racially ambiguous faces among
Figure 1. Mean d = memory score by target face race for children without and with essentialist reasoning about race. Error bars denote standard errors.
work should also examine whether these results generalize to children from other socioeconomic backgrounds. Finally, in the present work, we specifically examined memory performance for White, Black, and racially ambiguous Black– White faces. We selected these groups for this study because the specific history of Black–White relations in the United States makes Black individuals a highly salient racial category for White children around which they readily form implicit biases (Baron & Banaji, 2006). However, it is unclear whether racial essentialism would relate to children’s memory in a similar manner for other types of racially ambiguous faces. Research with adults shows that the boundary for categorizing faces as White or minority depends on the current racial hierarchy in the United States, such that individuals must have considerably more evidence to categorize a Black–White biracial individual as White compared with an Asian–White biracial individual (Ho et al., 2011). On the basis of these findings with adults, it is entirely possible that the current results might be less pronounced if we examined children’s mem- ory for Asian–White racially ambiguous faces. However, this conjecture is in need of direct empirical assessment. Complementing the role of emerging racial essentialism in the onset of stereotype use and more biased attitudes (e.g., Pauker, Ambady, & Apfelbaum, 2010; Ruble et al., 2004; Semaj, 1980), our findings demonstrate that emerging racial essentialism likely relates to more basic social perceptions of race: poor memory for racially ambiguous faces in children (an effect that resembles biases seen in adulthood; e.g., Pauker et al., 2009). Racial essen- tialist reasoning negatively predicts memory for racially ambigu- ous individuals, and children overlook racially ambiguous individ- uals in memory to the same extent that they overlook other outgroup members. These facts highlight the need for additional research on the perception and judgment of racially ambiguous children— one of the fastest growing populations in contemporary society.
Aboud, F. E. (1984). Social and cognitive bases of ethnic identity con- stancy. The Journal of Genetic Psychology: Research and Theory on Human Development, 145, 217–229. doi:10.1080/00221325. . Baron, A. S., & Banaji, M. R. (2006). The development of implicit attitudes: Evidence of race evaluations from ages 6, 10, and adulthood. Psychological Science, 17, 53–58. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280. .01664.x Bonam, C. M., & Shih, M. (2009). Exploring multiracial individuals’ comfort with intimate interracial relationships. Journal of Social Issues, 65, 87–103. doi:10.1111/j.1540-4560.2008.01589.x Chance, J. E., Turner, A. L., & Goldstein, A. G. (1982). Development of differential recognition for own- and other-race faces. The Journal of Psychology: Interdisciplinary and Applied, 112, 29 –37. doi:10.1080/ 00223980.1982. Chao, M. M., Hong, Y., & Chiu, C. (2013). Essentializing race: Its implications on racial categorization. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 104, 619 – 634. doi:10.1037/a Corneille, O., Huart, J., Becquart, E., & Brédart, S. (2004). When memory shifts toward more typical category exemplars: Accentuation effects in the recollection of ethnically ambiguous faces. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 86, 236 –250. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.86.2.
Cross, J. F., Cross, J., & Daly, J. (1971). Sex, race, age, and beauty as factors in recognition of faces. Perception & Psychophysics, 10, 393–
Keller, J. (2005). In genes we trust: The biological component of psycho- logical essentialism and its relationship to mechanisms of motivated social cognition. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 88, 686 –702. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.88.4. Killen, M., & Stangor, C. (2001). Children’s social reasoning about inclu- sion and exclusion in gender and race peer groups contexts. Child Development, 72, 174 –186. doi:10.1111/1467-8624. Kinzler, K. D., & Dautel, J. B. (2012). Children’s essentialist reasoning about language and race. Developmental Science, 15, 131–138. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-7687.2011.01101.x Levy, S. R., & Dweck, C. S. (1999). The impact of children’s static versus dynamic conceptions of people on stereotype formation. Child Devel- opment, 70, 1163–1180. doi:10.1111/1467-8624. Levy, S. R., Stroessner, S. J., & Dweck, C. S. (1998). Stereotype formation and endorsement: The role of implicit theories. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 74, 1421–1436. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.74. . Macmillan, N. A., & Creelman, C. D. (2005). Detection theory: A user’s guide (2nd ed.). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Maddox, K. B., & Gray, S. A. (2002). Cognitive representations of Black Americans: Reexploring the role of skin tone. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, 250 –259. doi:10.1177/ Markus, H. R. (2008). Pride, prejudice, and ambivalence: Toward a unified theory of race and ethnicity. American Psychologist, 63, 651– 670. doi:10.1037/0003-066X.63.8. Medin, D. L., & Ortony, A. (1989). Comments on Part I: Psychological essentialism. In S. Vosniadou & A. Ortony (Eds.), Similarity and ana- logical processing (pp. 179 –196). New York, NY: Cambridge Univer- sity Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511529863. Meissner, C. A., & Brigham, J. C. (2001). Thirty years of investigating the own-race bias in memory for faces: A meta-analytic review. Psychology, Public Policy, and Law, 7, 3–35. doi:10.1037/1076-8971.7.1. Pauker, K., & Ambady, N. (2009). Multiracial faces: How categorization affects memory at the boundaries of race. Journal of Social Issues, 65, 69 – 86. doi:10.1111/j.1540-4560.2008.01588.x Pauker, K., Ambady, N., & Apfelbaum, E. (2010). Race salience and essentialist thinking in racial stereotype development. Child Develop- ment, 81, 1799 –1813. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8624.2010.01511.x Pauker, K., Rule, N. O., & Ambady, N. (2010). Ambiguity and social perception. In E. Balcetis & D. Lassiter (Eds.), Social psychology of visual perception (pp. 7–26). New York, NY: Psychology Press. Pauker, K., Weisbuch, M., & Ambady, N. (2011, January). I’m comfort- able with racial ambiguity when it’s functionally important: Environ- mental constraints on processing racial ambiguity. In K. Savani & M. Weisbuch (Chairs), Manifest culture: An analysis of the psychological basis and influence of sociocultural landscapes. Symposium conducted at the 12th Annual Meeting of the Society for Personality and Social Psychology, San Antonio, TX. Pauker, K., Weisbuch, M., Ambady, N., Sommers, S. R., Adams, R. B., Jr., & Ivcevic, Z. (2009). Not so Black and White: Memory for ambiguous group members. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 96, 795– 810. doi:10.1037/a Peery, D., & Bodenhausen, G. V. (2008). Black White Black: Hypodescent in reflexive categorization of racially ambiguous faces. Psychological Science, 19, 973–977. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280. .02185.x Phinney, J. (1992). The multigroup ethnic identity measure: A new scale for use with diverse groups. Journal of Adolescent Research, 7, 156 –
Rhodes, M., & Gelman, S. A. (2009). A developmental examination of the conceptual structure of animal, artifact, and human social categories across two cultural contexts. Cognitive Psychology, 59, 244 –274. doi: 10.1016/j.cogpsych.2009.05. Rockquemore, K. A., & Laszloffy, T. A. (2005). Raising biracial children. Lanham, MD: AltaMira Press. Rothbart, M., & Taylor, M. (1992). Category labels and social reality: Do we view social categories as natural kinds? In G. R. Semin & K. Fiedler (Eds.), Language and social cognition (pp. 11–36). London, United Kingdom: Sage. Ruble, D. N., Alvarez, J., Bachman, M., Cameron, J., Fuligni, A., & Coll, C. G. (2004). The development of a sense of “we”: The emergence and implications of children’s collective identity. In M. Bennett & F. Sani (Eds.), The development of the social self (pp. 29 –76). East Sussex, United Kingdom: Psychology Press. Ruble, D. N., Taylor, L. J., Cyphers, L., Greulich, F. K., Lurye, L. E., & Shrout, P. E. (2007). The role of gender constancy in early gender development. Child Development, 78, 1121–1136. doi:10.1111/j.1467- 8624.2007.01056.x Sangrigoli, S., & de Schonen, S. (2004a). Effect of visual experience on face processing: Developmental study of inversion and non-native ef- fects. Developmental Science, 7, 74 – 87. doi:10.1111/j.1467-7687. .00324.x Sangrigoli, S., & de Schonen, S. (2004b). Recognition of own-race and other-race faces by three month old infants. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 45, 1219 –1227. doi:10.1111/j.1469-7610.2004.00319.x Sangrigoli, S., Pallier, C., Argenti, A.-M., Ventureyra, V. A. G., & de Schonen, S. (2005). Reversibility of the other-race effect in face recog- nition during childhood. Psychological Science, 16, 440 – 444. doi: 10.1111/j.0956-7976.2005.01554.x Semaj, L. T. (1980). The development of racial evaluation and preference: A cognitive approach. Journal of Black Psychology, 6, 59 –79. doi: 10.1177/ Shih, M., Bonam, C., Sanchez, D., & Peck, C. (2007). The social con- struction of race: Biracial identity and vulnerability to stereotypes. Cultural Diversity and Ethnic Minority Psychology, 13, 125–133. doi: 10.1037/1099-9809.13.2. Shutts, K., & Kinzler, K. (2007). An ambiguous-race illusion in children’s face memory. Psychological Science, 18, 763–767. doi:10.1111/j.1467- 9280.2007.01975.x Stanislaw, H., & Todorov, N. (1999). Calculation of signal detection theory measures. Behavior Research Methods, Instruments, & Computers, 31, 137–149. doi:10.3758/BF Taylor, M. G. (1996). The development of children’s beliefs about social and biological aspects of gender differences. Child Development, 67, 1555–1571. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8624.1996.tb01814.x Taylor, M. G., Rhodes, M., & Gelman, S. A. (2009). Boys will be boys; cows will be cows: Children’s essentialist reasoning about gender cat- egories and animal species. Child Development, 80, 461– 481. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8624.2009.01272.x Williams, M. J., & Eberhardt, J. L. (2008). Biological conceptions of race and the motivation to cross racial boundaries. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 94, 1033–1047. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.94.6. Yzerbyt, V., Rocher, S., & Schadron, G. (1997). Stereotypes as explana- tions: A subjective essentialistic view of group perception. In R. Spears, P. J. Oakes, N. Ellemers, & S. A. Haslam (Eds.), The social psychology of stereotyping and group life (pp. 20 –50). Cambridge, United King- dom: Blackwell.