Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

Genetic Diversity and Diversity of Environments, Lecture notes of Genetics

Genetic diversity and diversity of environments in Mendelian populations. The author talks about the gene pool of a population and how it can change due to various factors. The classical model is also discussed. The author expresses his difficulty in accepting some conclusions reached by mathematical geneticists due to implicit assumptions. a lecture note or study note.

Typology: Lecture notes

2021/2022

Uploaded on 05/11/2023

goldr4k3
goldr4k3 🇺🇸

4.4

(30)

286 documents

1 / 10

Toggle sidebar

This page cannot be seen from the preview

Don't miss anything!

bg1
GENETIC
DIVERSITY
AND
DIVERSITY
OF
ENVIRONMENTS
THEODOSIUS
DOBZHANSKY
THE
ROCKEFELLER
UNIVERSITY,
NEW
YORK
CITY
1.
Introduction
Like
many
ignorants,
I
have
my
deep
respect
for
mathematics
tinged
with
a
kind
of
superstitious
awe.
Using
their
recondite,
and
to
me
inscrutable
methods,
mathematicians
reach
conclusions
about
problems
of
genetics
and
evolution,
which
I
must
humbly
accept
as
following
inexorably
from
the
premises
and
the
assumptions
made.
I
hope,
however,
I
am
not
being
impertinent
if
I
say
that
not
all
of
these
conclusions
are
always
convincing.
The
difficulty
stems
from
the
premises
and
the
assumptions.
Most
exasperating
is
the
habit
of
certain
mathematical
geneticists
who
make
their
assumptions
implicit
rather
than
ex-
plicit,
on
the
ground
that
to
them
the
truth
of
their
assumptions
seems
self-
evident.
I
have
accepted
the
kind
invitation
of
Professor
Neyman
to
participate
in
this
Symposium
with
reluctance,
because
of
my
ignorance
of
mathematics;
all
I
can
talk
about
are
certain
self-evident,
and
certain
not
so
self-evident,
bio-
logical
premises
and
assumptions.
Let
us
restrict
our
attention
to
Mendelian
populations.
Mendelian
popula-
tions
are
reproductive
communities
of
sexual
and
either
obligatorily
or
at
least
facultatively
cross
fertilizing
organisms.
This
leaves
out
of
account
the
asexual,
exclusively
self-fertilizing,
parthenogenetic
organisms,
as
well
as
some
inter-
mediate
situations
in
which
cross
fertilization
is
rare.
A
Mendelian
population
is
said
to
have
a
corporate
genotype
or
gene
pool.
The
gene
pool
of
a
population
may
be
envisaged
as
the
genes
in
the
array
of
the
gametes,
sex
cells,
which
give
rise
to
the
following
generation.
The
composition
of
the
gene
pool
can
be
de-
scribed
in
terms
of
the
numbers
or
of
the
frequencies
of
the
genes
and
linked
gene
complexes.
The
mechanisms
of
the
replication
of
the
hereditary
materials
tend
to
make
the
gene
pool
constant
generation
after
generation.
Mutation,
recombination,
selection,
sampling
errors
in
small
populations,
vicissitudes
of
the
environments,
and
variations
of
the
reproductive
habits
and
opportunities
are
liable
to
change
the
composition
of
the
gene
pool.
2.
The
classical
model
Let
us
begin
with
a
model
which
is
probably
the
simplest,
thoroughly
un-
realistic
biologically,
tractable
mathematically,
and,
therefore,
the
favorite
with
some
mathematical
geneticists
anld
genetical
mathematicians.
Assume
a
Men-
295
pf3
pf4
pf5
pf8
pf9
pfa

Partial preview of the text

Download Genetic Diversity and Diversity of Environments and more Lecture notes Genetics in PDF only on Docsity!

GENETIC DIVERSITY^ AND^ DIVERSITY

OF ENVIRONMENTS

THEODOSIUS DOBZHANSKY

THE ROCKEFELLER UNIVERSITY, NEW YORK CITY

  1. Introduction

Like many ignorants, I have my deep respect for mathematics tinged with

a kind of superstitious awe. Using their recondite, and to me inscrutable methods,

mathematicians reach conclusions about problems of genetics and evolution,

which I must humbly accept as following inexorably from the premises and the

assumptions made. I^ hope, however, I am not being impertinent if I say that

not all of these conclusions are always convincing. The difficulty stems from

the premises and the assumptions. Most exasperating is the habit of certain

mathematical geneticists who make their assumptions implicit rather than ex-

plicit, on the ground that to them the truth of their assumptions seems self-

evident. I have accepted the kind invitation of Professor Neyman to participate

in this Symposium with reluctance, because of my ignorance of mathematics;

all I can talk about are certain self-evident, and certain not so self-evident, bio-

logical premises and assumptions.

Let us restrict our attention to Mendelian populations. Mendelian popula-

tions are reproductive communities of sexual and either obligatorily or at least

facultatively cross fertilizing organisms. This leaves out of account the asexual,

exclusively self-fertilizing, parthenogenetic organisms, as well^ as some inter-

mediate situations^ in^ which^ cross^ fertilization^ is^ rare.^ A^ Mendelian^ population

is said^ to^ have^ a^ corporate genotype or^ gene pool. The gene pool of^ a^ population

may be^ envisaged as^ the^ genes in^ the^ array^ of the^ gametes,^ sex^ cells,^ which^ give

rise to^ the^ following generation. The^ composition of^ the^ gene pool^ can^ be^ de- scribed in terms of the numbers or of the (^) frequencies of the genes and linked gene complexes. The^ mechanisms^ of^ the^ replication^ of the^ hereditary^ materials tend to make the (^) gene pool constant (^) generation after (^) generation. Mutation, recombination, selection, sampling errors in small populations, vicissitudes of the environments, and variations of the reproductive habits and opportunities are liable to change the composition of the gene pool.

2. The classical model

Let us begin with a model which is probably the simplest, thoroughly un-

realistic biologically, tractable mathematically, and, therefore, the favorite with some mathematical geneticists anld genetical mathematicians. Assume a Men- 295

296 FIFTH BERKELEY SYMPOSIUM: DOBZHANSKY

delian population for which (a) the environment is constant in time and in

space for all members of the population; (b) the variable gene loci are each

represented by two or more alleles, one allele being "normal" and beneficial in

the environment, and all other alleles more or less disadvantageous in homozy-

gotes; (c) most of the gene loci are occupied by identical alleles in all individuals,

the variable loci are a minority; (d) the genes produce their effects each in-

dependently of the^ others; epistatic interactions, especially as concerns fitness,

do not occur or are negligible; the fitness variations caused by the alleles at the

unfixed loci are simply additive or multiplicative; (e) the population size is

infinite or large enough to be treated as such.

Genetic uniformity is clearly the ideal state under the above model. Natural,

artificial, or eugenic selection should eliminate all disadvantageous genotypes,

and establish the single optimal homozygous genotype. All members of the

population will be genetically identical, and all optimally fit. This paragon of

adaptive virtues is difficult to achieve because of mutation. In the absence of

known means to suppress all mutation, genetic variants, all or nearly all dele-

terious, will be injected into the gene pool in every generation. The fitness of

the population will always lag below the optimum. How far below will be

relatively easy to determine. If the mutation rates and the loss of fitness caused

by each mutant are known, the genetic equilibria of the mutants can be pre-

dicted. The magnitude of the genetic load which a population carries can be

estimated, as^ well^ as the^ numbers^ of the^ "genetic deaths" which^ the population

will suffer. These numbers can be made as frightening as you wish, especially

if you forget to state that a genetic death does not always produce a cadaver.

Having no children makes you genetically dead, having one child makes you

genetically half dead.

The model outlined makes all genetic diversity unwelcome departure from

the ideal optimal uniformity. Is it at all conceivable that this Platonic archetypal

state may ever be achieved? It is conceivable, but at a cost of truly heroic meas-

ures. The first is abandonment of sexual reproduction. A technique may con-

ceivably be invented to stimulate the development of human diploid cells from

a tissue culture to yield embryos and eventually adult bodies. Such a feat has

indeed been accomplished with cells of a lowly plant, the wild carrot. Assuming,

then, that^ one encounters^ and^ recognizes the carrier of the^ optimal genotype of

the species, obtains a tissue culture of his cells, avoids all mutation, makes the

cells develop without meiosis and fertilization, and accepts the genetic identity

as not (^) unbearably dull, then the "ideal" (^) mankind, or (^) any other (^) species, is

conceivable. This ideal is implicit in some eugenical writings, although their

authors (^) explicitly disclaim the (^) advocacy of any such ideal.

3. Requirements to be met by a more realistic model

3.1. Heterotic balance. Suppose now^ that some gene loci^ produce more^ than a single beneficial allele.^ Overdominance makes the^ heterozygote A1A2 not^ inter-

298 FIFTH BERKELEY SYMPOSIUM: DOBZHANSKY

same geographic locality. The environmental changes may be cyclic and recur-

ring regularly within a single generation of an organism or in different genera-

tions. Seasonal changes are an obvious example. Or, they may be recurrent in

space rather than in time, as with different food plants or other food sources

that may be present in a locality in which a population dependent upon these

food sources lives. This situation is sometimes described as the occupation of

a variety of ecological niches by a population. Some species of organisms and

some populations have a greater and others a more limited variety of ecological

niches available to them.

Abandonment of the assumption of environmental uniformity, and substitu-

tion of environmental diversity results in models of population structure that

are uncomfortably complex and relatively intractable. These are good reasons

why mathematicians as well as geneticists are reluctant to deal with them.

Unfortunately, nature has not been kind enough to make all things as simple

as we would like them to be. Complexities have to be faced. We know much

less about population genetics than is still unknown. To pretend otherwise is

to retard acquisition of more satisfactory knowledge. Among the colleagues

participating in the present Symposium, Bodmer, Dempster, and Levene have

made some pioneering studies of the consequences of environmental diversity;

they will not consider my saying that they have barely scratched the surface

an impertinence.

There are, in general, two ways of being adapted to environmental diversity.

One is physiological or developmental homeostasis. The other is genetic diversi-

fication, in which different genotypes within a population, or different popula-

tions, are adaptively specialized to^ fit^ different ecological niches^ or^ different

environmental contingencies. Maintenance of^ a^ constant body temperature de-

spite temperature changes in^ the^ environment is^ a^ good example of^ physiological

homeostasis; dependence of^ the^ body size^ in^ adult insects^ on^ the^ amount^ of^ food

available to^ nymphs or^ larvae is^ an^ instance^ of^ developmental homeostasis. Presence in^ a^ population of^ genetic variants with different^ food^ preferences, different temperature tolerances, and^ so^ forth, permits a^ fuller utilization^ of^ the environmental opportunities than^ could^ be^ achieved^ by a^ single genotype. Brazenly opportunistic, evolution^ utilizes^ homeostatic^ plasticity as^ well^ as genetic specialization and diversification^ to^ achieve^ adaptedness in^ its^ creations.

Is either of these methods superior to the other? It is intuitively obvious that a

genotype which could^ react^ to^ every^ environment^ by^ producing optimal pheno-

types would be ideal. This would, indeed, be that will-o'-the-wisp invented by some geneticists, the optimal genotype. Ours is, however, not only not the most

perfect of all conceivable worlds but not even^ the best of all^ possible worlds.

The adaptive capabilities of^ every genotype are^ circumscribed, more or^ less widely or narrowly. This makes^ adaptation by means^ of^ genetic diversification

sometimes preferable. In^ general, the^ more^ diversified^ is the environment the

less (^) likely is a (^) genotype fit to (^) occupy all the available (^) ecological niches. The problems that arise^ are^ those^ of^ evolutionary^ strategies.^ Mathematicians and

GENETIC (^) DIVERSITY 299

geneticists can play imagining themselves being gods, aiid decide what strategy

evolution could have used to achieve adaptedness most rapidly and effectively.

The optimal strategy would, of course, yield the most perfect possible adapted-

ness of a population to its environments. Such a strategy could, conceivably,

rely on a homeostatic plasticity given by a single or a few genotypes, or could

make use of an adaptive genetic polymorphism, or various combinations of these

methods. Levins [22], [23], [24] and Lewontin [26], [27], have produced very

interesting studies of optimal evolutionary strategies. There evidently exist

many fascinating and challenging problems in this field, both for theoreticians

and for experimentalists. One may inquire how evolution could be made adap-

tively most productive, and one may wish to find out whether evolution has

in actuality utilized anything resembling the methods which our mathematical

and biological wisdom indicates as most advisable.

Recognition of the importance of environmental diversity necessitates con-

sideration of some forms of selection which are rather more complex than the

classical ones. Although they were considered by the pioneers of mathematical

genetics, especially by Sewall Wright [47], [48], much remains to be done to

achieve a satisfactory understanding, both by way of mathematical models and

of their experimental applications. Suppose that there are two or more pheno-

types which confer a high Darwinian fitness on their possessors, while the

intermediates between them are less fit, or are culled and prevented from

reproducing by the breeder. This is diversifying selection, which will tend to

make the population genetically variable or polymorphic. (It is also termed

"disruptive" selection, which is a most unfortunate choice of word, since this

selection is biologically constructive rather than disruptive.) One of the situa-

tions in which diversifying selection will occur is when the fitness of a genotype

is a function of its frequency; in other words, the selection coefficient s is a

function of the gene frequency q.

An interesting, though perhaps rather special, example of this is the advantage

in mating of a type which is rare, and disadvantage of a type which is common

in a given environment. In the experiments of my colleague, Dr. Lee Ehrman

[13], females and males of two strains of Drosophila pseudoobscura are intro-

duced into an observation chamber, and the matings that occur are recorded.

The following data were obtained using strains derived from wild flies collected

in California (C) and flies collected in Texas (T). The numbers of the flies of

each sex (^) per chamber, the numbers of (^) females and of (^) males that mated (of course, in^ several chambers), and the chi squares (one degree of freedom) testing

the deviation from randomness of mating, are summarized in table I.

In Drosophila, males court all females rather (^) indiscriminately, but females accept only some and (^) reject other (^) courtships. Observed (^) courtships are several times more numerous than copulations in the observation chambers. (^) Now, with C and T females and males being equally numerous in a chamber, the C and T

flies mate about equally frequently; when C are four times more numerous

than (^) T, the number of C males (^) copulating is (^) only twice that of T (^) males; when

GENETIC DIVERSITY 301

biologists given to this possibility that I am unable to find in the literature a

convincing case that could be used here as an illustration.

There are, to be sure, excellent data of Birch on three species of the grain beetles Calandra and the related genus Rhizopertha, of Park^ [34]^ and his school

and of Lerner [17] and his colleagues on two species of the flour beetles Tribolium,

and of Moore [32] on two species of Drosophila. In all these studies, it has

been found that one species is better adapted to a certain food, or to a certain

temperature or humidity than the other species, while this latter is superior

under different conditions. In mixed populations one or the other species is

usually the winner, depending upon the environment. Most^ fascinating are the

recently published experiments of^ Sokoloff, Lerner and^ Ho^ [43] on^ mixed^ cul-

tures of^ Tribolium castaneum^ and^ T.^ confusum. The^ first of^ these^ does^ better

than the second on^ wheat^ flour, while^ the^ second^ does better^ in^ cornmeal.^ When

in competition on corn, castaneum is, however, the winner as long as confusum

is also present, but when the competitor is eliminated, the winner goes into

decline too. The solution of the puzzle is that these beetles are cannibals, and

while suffering from a nutritional deficiency on corn, castaneum is able to supple-

ment its diet by eating developmental stages of confusum. When the supply of

the latter species is exhausted, the^ species practicing "xenocide" commits un-

witting suicide.

In humid tropics, where there^ are^ many species of^ Drosophila developing^ in

fermenting fruits, Pipkin [40] and^ others^ found^ a^ remarkable differentiation^ of

ecological preferences. Although most^ species of^ Drosophila^ can^ feed^ on most

species of^ fruits,^ each^ Drosophila^ has^ a^ certain^ repertory^ of^ fruits which^ it

chooses if choice is available. This is an admirable arrangement, because when

there is a choice of fruits, different Drosophilae go after different fruits, thus

minimizing competition. The preference does not, however, reach the point

when a Drosophila could develop only in a single kind of fruit; so rigorous a

specialization would evidently endanger the continuation of^ the species if its

food source were owing to some^ accident^ temporarily unavailable. Differential

food preferences almost certainly exist^ within^ species as^ well, but the evidence

for this is^ circumstantial^ and^ inconclusive.

The evolutionary situations which arise when a Mendelian populationl faces

a diversity of environments^ have^ been^ surprisingly neglected by biologists, and perhaps because of this^ neglected also^ by mathematicians. Environments may vary in^ time, or^ in^ space, or^ both.^ Variation^ in^ time^ may^ be^ regularly^ cyclic,^ as

with seasons, or irregular, like wet and drought years. Variations in^ space may

recur mosaic fashion, as meadows, forests, and hill^ slopes in^ many countries,

or may be more systematic, as with the^ rainfall becoming greater or^ more scarce

as one approaches the ocean or^ ascends^ to^ higher altitudes^ in^ the mountains.

How will the population genotypes respond to these challenges? Under what

conditions will stably balanced polymorphisms be established? In a two page

article published some 13 years ago, Levene [18] has shown that when two or

302 FIFTH BERKELEY SYMPOSIUM: DOBZHANSKY

more ecological niches are available, two or more alleles may be held in stable

polymorphic equilibria, without the heterozygotes being heterotic. Dempster

[10], Li^ [29],^ [30],^ Lewontin^ [25],^ [27], [28],^ Haldane^ and^ Jayakar [14],^ Parsons

[35] to [39], and others have discussed Levene's and some other models. The

"polymorphism due to selection in varying direction" examined briefly by

Haldane and Jaykar seems particularly interesting, although it remains to be

discovered how often the biological situation postulated by them is encountered

in nature. They assumed a pair of alleles, one of which is dominant and the

other recessive, each of which makes its carrier fitter than its counterpart in

different generations. Now, if the arithmetic mean of the fitnesses of the^ re-

cessives in (^) different generations is greater than unity, while the geometric mean

is lower than unity, both alleles will persist in the population owing to this form

of balancing selection.

Very little^ attention^ has been^ given^ to^ the effects^ of^ epistatic^ interactions^ of

different genes affecting fitness. That such interactions occur, both for loci in

different chromosomes^ and for linked^ loci, is^ not^ denied^ by anyone; how^ preva-

lent epistatic phenomena are in reality is, however, an open question. I leave

it to you to judge whether it^ is advisable^ to^ build^ theories^ of^ population^ genetics

ignoring epistasis. Bodmer and^ Parsons^ [5],^ Lewontin^ and^ Kojima^ [28],^ and

some others have made theoretical studies of the situations that may arise

when linked genes affect fitness differentially when in coupling and when in

repulsion phase. As far^ as^ I^ know,^ epistasis^ by^ itself,^ without^ linkage^ or^ heterosis,

has not been shown to yield stable polymorphisms. The situations that might

arise when diversifying selection operates with epistatically interacting loci are,

however, in need of investigation.

4. Concluding remarks

I realize how unsatisfactory this article may appear to you. I have tossed

before you a host of problems, and have given no solution for any of them.

To give solutions was, however, not within my ambition, because this is beyond

my capabilities. The intention was rather to ask the^ mathematical^ colleagues

for help, which geneticists and evolutionists are so much in need. The classical

model of genetic population structure has until recently received the^ lion's^ share

of attention. It has the^ advantage of^ simplicity, but the^ disadvantage of^ mis-

representing reality. It is^ not^ entirely played out, and^ probably never^ will^ be,

since it does contain^ a^ grain of truth-for^ some^ genes and for^ some^ environments

its simplifying assumptions are^ satisfactory as^ approximations. But the bio-

logical reality is^ different, and if I may say so, more^ interesting than the classical

model suggests. Natural^ populations of^ many sexual^ species, including man, contain so much (^) genetic diversity at so (^) many loci that two individuals probably never have the same (^) genotypes, unless they are identical twins. Moreover, a good part of this diversity is not a sad accident, not a^ departure from^ this Platonic eidos called the (^) "optimum genotype," but^ a means^ whereby the^ popu-

304 FIFTH BERKELEY SYMPOSIIJM: DOBZHANSKY

Berkeley and^ Los^ Angeles, University^ of^ California Press,^ 1967,^ Vol.^ 4,^ pp.^ 305-316. [21] H. LEVENE, I. M.^ LERNER,^ A.^ SOKOLOFF,^ F.^ K.^ Ho,^ anid^ I. R.^ FRANKLIN,^ "Genetic^ load in Tribolium," Proc.^ Nat. Acad. Sci.^ U.S.A., Vol. 53^ (1965),^ pp.^ 1042-1050. [22] R. LEVINS, "The^ theory^ of^ fitness^ in^ a^ heterogeneous^ environiment.^ I.^ The^ fitness^ set and adaptive^ function,"^ Amer.^ Natur.,^ Vol.^96 (1962),^ pp. 361-373. [23] ,^ "The theory^ of^ fitness^ in^ a^ heterogeneous^ environment. II.^ Developmental flexibility and niche selection," Amer. Natur.,^ Vol.^97 (1963),^ pp.^ 75-90. [24] , "The^ theory^ of^ fitness^ in^ a^ heterogeneous^ environment. IV. The^ adaptive^ sig- nificance of the gene flow," Evolution, Vol.^18 (1964),^ pp.^ 635-638. [25] R. C. LEWONTIN, "The adaptation^ of^ populations^ to^ varying^ environments,"^ Cold^ Spring Harbor Symp. Quant.^ Biol.,^ Vol.^22 (1957),^ pp.^ 395-408. [26] ,"Evolution and^ the theory of^ games,"^ J.^ l'heoret. Biol.,^ Vol.^1 (1961),^ pp.^ 382-403. [27] ,^ "The interaction of^ selection and^ linkage.^ I.^ General^ considerations;^ heterotic models," Genetics,^ Vol.^49 (1964),^ pp.^ 49-67. [28] R. C. LEWONTIN and^ K.^ KOJIMA,^ "The^ evolutioniary^ dynamiiics^ of^ complex^ polymor- phisms," Evolution,^ Vol.^14 (1960),^ pp.^ 458-472. [29] C. C. Li, Population Genetics,^ Chicago,^ University^ of^ Chicago^ Press, 1955. [30] , "Decrease of^ population fitness^ upon^ inbreeding,"^ Proc.^ Nat.^ Acad.^ Sci.^ U.S.A., Vol. 49 (1963), pp. 439-445. [31] , "The^ way^ the^ load^ ratio^ works,"^ Amer.^ J.^ Hum.^ Genet.,^ Vol.^15 (1963),^ pp. 316-321. [32] J.^ A. MOORE,^ "Competition^ between Drosophila^ melanogaster^ and^ Drosophila^ simulans. I. Population cage experiments," Evolution, Vol.^6 (1952),^ pp.^ 407-420. [33] N.^ E. MORTON, "The^ mutational^ load^ due^ to^ detrimental^ genes^ in^ man,"^ Amer.^ J. Hum. Genet., Vol. 12 (1960), pp.^ 348-364. [34] T.^ PARK,^ P.^ H.^ LESLIE,^ anid^ I).^ B. MERTZ,^ "Genetic^ strains^ and^ competition^ in^ popula- tions of Tribolium," Physiol. Zool.,^ Vol.^37 (1964),^ pp. 97-162. [35] P. A. PARSONS, "Dependence of^ genotypic^ viabilities^ on^ co-existing^ genotypes^ in^ Dro- sophila," Heredity, Vol. 13 (1959),^ pp.^ 393-402. [36] "The^ initial^ increase^ of^ a new^ gene^ under^ positive^ assortative^ mating,"^ Heredity, Vol. 17 (1962), pp. 267-276. [37] ,^ "Migration^ as^ a^ factor^ in^ natural^ selection,"^ Genetica,^ Vol.^33 (1963),^ pp.^ 184-206. [38] ,^ "Polymorphism and^ the^ balanced polygenic^ combinations,"^ Evolution,^ Vol.^17 (1963), pp. 564-574. [39] ,^ "Interaction within^ and between^ chromosomes,"^ J.^ Theoret.^ Biol.,^ Vol.^6 (1964), pp. 208-216. [40] S. B. PIPKIN, "The influence^ of^ adult^ and^ larval^ food^ habits^ on^ population^ size of^ neo- tropical ground-feeding Drosophila,"^ Amer.^ Midland^ Natur.,^ Vol. 74^ (1965),^ pp. 1-27. [41] L. D. SANGHVI, "The^ concept of^ genetic^ load.^ A^ critique,"^ Amer. J. Hum.^ Genet.,^ Vol.^15 (1962), pp. 298-309. [42] W. J. SCHULL and^ J.^ V.^ NEEL,^ The^ Effects^ of^ Inbreeding^ on^ Japanese^ Children,^ New^ York, Harper &^ Row,^ 1965. [43] A. SOKOLOFF, I.^ M.^ LERNER, and^ F.^ K. Ho,^ "Self-elimination^ of^ Tribolium^ castaneum following xenocide^ of^ T.^ confusunm," Amer.^ Natur., Vol. 99^ (1965),^ pp.^ 399-404. [44] B.^ WALLACE, "The^ average^ effect^ of^ radiation-induced^ mutations^ on^ viability^ in^ Dro- sophila melanogaster," Evolution, Vol.^12 (1958),^ pp.^ 532-556. [45] "Temporal^ changes^ in the^ roles^ of^ lethal and^ semilethal^ chromosomes^ within populations of^ Drosophila^ melanogaster,"^ Amer.^ Natur.,^ Vol.^96 (1962),^ pp. 247-256. [46] ,^ "Genetic^ diversity,^ genetic^ uniformity,^ and heterosis,"^ Canad. J.^ Genet.^ Cytol., Vol. 5 (1963), pp. 239-253. [47] S. WRIGHT, "Evolution^ in^ Mendelian^ populations,"^ Genetics,^ Vol. 16^ (1931),^ pp.^ 97-159. [48] ,"Classification of the factors of^ evolution,"^ Cold^ Spring^ Harbor^ Symp.^ Quant. Biol., Vol.^20 (1955),^ pp.^ 16-24.