Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

Kripke's Naming & Necessity: Rigid Designators & Necessity Distinction, Study notes of Literature

In this document, saul kripke explores the nature of names and their relationship to necessity and a priori knowledge. He argues that names are rigid designators, meaning they refer to the same object in every possible world, and that they cannot have the same meaning as non-rigid designators or descriptions. Kripke also introduces the conceptual distinction between necessity and a priori knowledge, and provides examples of necessary a posteriori and contingent a priori propositions. He challenges the classical theory that the meanings of names are the same as the descriptions associated with them, and proposes an alternative theory of how the reference of names is fixed.

What you will learn

  • How does Kripke distinguish between necessity and a priori knowledge?
  • What is the difference between rigid and non-rigid designators?
  • What is the alternative theory of name reference proposed by Kripke?

Typology: Study notes

2021/2022

Uploaded on 09/27/2022

myafen
myafen 🇬🇧

4.3

(8)

300 documents

1 / 4

Toggle sidebar

This page cannot be seen from the preview

Don't miss anything!

bg1
Kripke’s Naming and Necessity
Some theses of Naming and Necessity
1. Names are rigid designators. If a name refers to an object o, it refers to o
with respect to every possible world (in which oexists).
2. If one expression is a rigid and another is not, they cannot mean the same
thing. Since the descriptions ordinarily associated with names by speakers
are not rigid designators, they cannot give the meanings of those names.
3. There is a distinction between giving the meaning of an expression and saying
how its reference is determined (or fixed).
4. While (in cases of ordinary proper names) descriptions never give the mean-
ings of names, sometimes they play a role in the way that the reference of a
name is fixed.
5. Typically, an account of how the reference of a name is fixed consists of two
parts: an account of how the name was introduced to have a certain reference,
and an account of how the name maintained, or kept, that reference. Names
are usually introduced either by ostension or by description. Typically, their
reference is maintained by a historical chain of people intending to use the
name in the same way as their predecessors.
6. There is a conceptual distinction between necessity and a prioricity. A claim
is necessarily true if and only if the world could not have been such as to
make it false. A claim is knowable a priori just in case someone could know
it to be true without appeal to empirical evidence. We can say that necessity
is a metaphysical property of claims (i.e., propositions), whereas a prioricity
is an epistemological property of them.
7. Some propositions are both contingent and a priori. E.g., the proposition
expressed by ‘Stick S is one meter long’, in the scenario envisaged by Kripke.
8. Some propositions are both necessary and a posteriori. E.g., the proposition
expressed by ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus.’
1
pf3
pf4

Partial preview of the text

Download Kripke's Naming & Necessity: Rigid Designators & Necessity Distinction and more Study notes Literature in PDF only on Docsity!

Kripke’s Naming and Necessity

Some theses of Naming and Necessity

  1. Names are rigid designators. If a name refers to an object o, it refers to o with respect to every possible world (in which o exists).
  2. If one expression is a rigid and another is not, they cannot mean the same thing. Since the descriptions ordinarily associated with names by speakers are not rigid designators, they cannot give the meanings of those names.
  3. There is a distinction between giving the meaning of an expression and saying how its reference is determined (or fixed).
  4. While (in cases of ordinary proper names) descriptions never give the mean- ings of names, sometimes they play a role in the way that the reference of a name is fixed.
  5. Typically, an account of how the reference of a name is fixed consists of two parts: an account of how the name was introduced to have a certain reference, and an account of how the name maintained, or kept, that reference. Names are usually introduced either by ostension or by description. Typically, their reference is maintained by a historical chain of people intending to use the name in the same way as their predecessors.
  6. There is a conceptual distinction between necessity and a prioricity. A claim is necessarily true if and only if the world could not have been such as to make it false. A claim is knowable a priori just in case someone could know it to be true without appeal to empirical evidence. We can say that necessity is a metaphysical property of claims (i.e., propositions), whereas a prioricity is an epistemological property of them.
  7. Some propositions are both contingent and a priori. E.g., the proposition expressed by ‘Stick S is one meter long’, in the scenario envisaged by Kripke.
  8. Some propositions are both necessary and a posteriori. E.g., the proposition expressed by ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus.’

Kripke’s three arguments against the view that the meanings of names are the same as the meanings of descriptions associated with those names by speakers

The modal argument

  1. Proper names are rigid designators.
  2. The definite descriptions associated with names by speakers are typically not rigid designators.
  3. If an expression is a rigid designator, then it cannot mean the same as any expression which is non-rigid. C. The meanings of names are typically not the same as the meanings of definite descriptions associated with them by speakers.

The semantic argument

  1. The meaning of a name determines its reference.
  2. Often, the descriptions associated with a name by speakers refer to something different than the name, or nothing at all. C. In at least these cases, the meanings of names are not the same as the meanings of definite descriptions associated with them by speakers.

The epistemic argument

  1. If an expression x means the same as another expression y, then x may be substituted for y in any sentence without changing the truth value of that sentence.
  2. In the case of a proper name N and a definite description D associated with N by speakers, it is knowable a priori that D is D will be true even though it is knowable a priori that N is D is false. C. In such cases, the meanings of names are not the same as the meanings of definite descriptions associated with them by speakers.

Outline of Naming and Necessity

The Frege-Russsell picture of names and its strengths (26-29)

Three arguments for the classical, descriptivist picture of names:

  1. It explains how the references of names are determined.
  2. It explains Frege’s puzzle about identity statements.
  3. It explains what’s going on with negative existentials.

A problem for the classical theory, and the move to ‘cluster’ descriptivism (30-32)

The distinction between necessity and the a priori (34-39)

Kripke introduces the conceptual distinction between necessity and a prioricity without yet arguing that there are any propositions which fall into one category

John’s mother introduced his name in a slightly unusual way, by saying ‘Let ‘John’ be the name of the cute boy wearing stripes in the crib.’ This could be part of the way that the reference of the name is fixed; but it would not seem to follow that ‘John’ means the same as ‘the cute boy wearing stripes in the crib.’

Outline of the ‘cluster’ theory (61-67)

[SKIP]

Descriptivism and the threat of circularity (68-70)

[SKIP]

The semantic argument (78-85)

Discussion of the examples of ‘Cicero’, ‘Feynman’, ‘Einstein’ and other names used to refer to individuals by speakers who do not possess any descriptions which pick out those individuals.

The epistemic argument (86-87)

[see above]

Kripke’s ‘alternative picture’ (88-97)

We began this discussion by noting several arguments in favor of the classical theory of names. One of these which seemed particularly powerful was that it gives a story about how the reference of names is determined. Kripke reiterates this argument for the classical descriptivist picture on p. 80.

Kripke gives an alternative story about how the reference of names is fixed. The way he tells the story, it breaks into two parts: (i) an account of how the reference of a name is initially determined, when the name is introduced; and (ii) an account of how the reference of names is maintained over time.

Remember: Kripke distinguished between the meaning of a name and what fixes its reference. This may be a good account of what fixes the reference of a name; but, as yet, we have no positive account of the meanings of names. Kripke never provides such a positive account.

Identity statements (96-105)

Identity statements are, Kripke claims, an example of the necessary a posteriori. That they are necessary follows from the fact that names are rigid designators; but they seem to be a posteriori, since ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’, for example, seems to express something which is knowable only on the basis of empirical evidence.