Docsity
Docsity

Prepare for your exams
Prepare for your exams

Study with the several resources on Docsity


Earn points to download
Earn points to download

Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan


Guidelines and tips
Guidelines and tips

The Influence of Enlightenment-Era Theories on Modern Commons Theory and Property Law, Study notes of Civil procedure

This article explores the significant impact of early modern theories of societal evolution, specifically stadial theory, on the development of modern commons theory and property law. The author argues that property law has played a central role in these theories since the Enlightenment era, shaping the way we think about law, property, and government. influential thinkers like John Dalrymple, William Blackstone, and Garret Hardin, and their contributions to the evolution of property theory.

What you will learn

  • What impact did the evolution of property institutions have on societal development, according to stadial theory?
  • How did stadial theory shape modern commons theory and property law?
  • How did opponents of the normative claims of stadial theory frame their arguments?
  • Who were some of the key thinkers in the development of stadial theory and property law?
  • What were the arguments for and against the progression of property institutions in stadial theory?

Typology: Study notes

2021/2022

Uploaded on 03/31/2022

tylar
tylar 🇺🇸

4.8

(19)

240 documents

1 / 26

Toggle sidebar

This page cannot be seen from the preview

Don't miss anything!

bg1
507
Savagery, Civilization, and
Property: Theories of Societal
Evolution and Commons Theory
David B. Schorr*
This article argues that modern commons theory has been substantially
shaped by early modern ways of thinking about the evolution of
civilizations. In particular, it has hewed closely to models that
gelled in the Enlightenment-era works known as “stadial theory,”
by authors such as Lord Kames and Adam Smith, and passed down
to the twentieth century, to theorists including Garrett Hardin,
Harold Demsetz, and Elinor Ostrom. It argues that stadial thinking
reached modern commons theorists largely through the disciplines
of anthropology and human ecology, paying particular attention
to the debate among anthropologists over aboriginal property
rights, colonial and international development discourse, and neo-
Malthusian conservationism. The effects of stadial theories’ influence
include a belief among many that private property represents a more
advanced stage of civilization than does the commons; and among
others a Romantic yearning to return to an Eden of primitive and
community-based commons. Thus do deep cultural attitudes, rooted
in the speculative thinking of an earlier age, color todayʼs theories
— positive and normative — of the commons.
* Senior Lecturer, Buchmann Faculty of Law, Tel Aviv University. Thanks to
Sharon Kingsland, Fabien Locher, Lucy McCann, Michel Morin, Carol Rose,
and Natty Wolloch for their helpful suggestions, and to Elizabeth Cox and Aviya
Basha for research assistance.
This research was supported by the Israel Science Foundation (grant no. 1822/16).
Cite as: David B. Schorr, Savagery, Civilization, and Property: Theories of
Societal Evolution and Commons Theory, 19 T
heoreTical
i
nquiries
L. 507
(2018).
pf3
pf4
pf5
pf8
pf9
pfa
pfd
pfe
pff
pf12
pf13
pf14
pf15
pf16
pf17
pf18
pf19
pf1a

Partial preview of the text

Download The Influence of Enlightenment-Era Theories on Modern Commons Theory and Property Law and more Study notes Civil procedure in PDF only on Docsity!

Savagery, Civilization, and

Property: Theories of Societal

Evolution and Commons Theory

David B. Schorr*

This article argues that modern commons theory has been substantially

shaped by early modern ways of thinking about the evolution of

civilizations. In particular, it has hewed closely to models that

gelled in the Enlightenment-era works known as “stadial theory,”

by authors such as Lord Kames and Adam Smith, and passed down

to the twentieth century, to theorists including Garrett Hardin,

Harold Demsetz, and Elinor Ostrom. It argues that stadial thinking

reached modern commons theorists largely through the disciplines

of anthropology and human ecology, paying particular attention

to the debate among anthropologists over aboriginal property

rights, colonial and international development discourse, and neo-

Malthusian conservationism. The effects of stadial theories’ influence

include a belief among many that private property represents a more

advanced stage of civilization than does the commons; and among

others a Romantic yearning to return to an Eden of primitive and

community-based commons. Thus do deep cultural attitudes, rooted

in the speculative thinking of an earlier age, color todayʼs theories

— positive and normative — of the commons.

  • Senior Lecturer, Buchmann Faculty of Law, Tel Aviv University. Thanks to Sharon Kingsland, Fabien Locher, Lucy McCann, Michel Morin, Carol Rose, and Natty Wolloch for their helpful suggestions, and to Elizabeth Cox and Aviya Basha for research assistance. This research was supported by the Israel Science Foundation (grant no. 1822/16). Cite as: David B. Schorr, Savagery, Civilization, and Property: Theories of Societal Evolution and Commons Theory , 19 T heoreTical inquiries L. 507 (2018).

508 Theoretical Inquiries in Law [Vol. 19.2:

I ntroductIon

This article makes a simple claim: that the commons theory of the last half

century, in its various forms and schools, has been substantially shaped by early

modern ways of thinking about the evolution of civilizations. In particular,

it has hewed closely to models that gelled in the Enlightenment-era works

known as “stadial theory,” passed down to the twentieth century through the

disciplines of anthropology and human ecology, and strongly entrenched in

the patterns of thought of property theorists to this day.

I do not wish to argue that recent thinkers deliberately or consciously based

their theories on early modern precedents, nor do I claim that their theories

simply recast old theories, pouring old wine into new bottles. What I wish to

argue, rather, is that modern commons theory is a series of variations on a theme,

the theme being the passage of human societies from stages of “barbarism”

or “savagery” to “civilization.” This way of thinking, largely elaborated in

the eighteenth century, has proved to be so powerful that it continues to shape

the discourse around common property and environmental commons into the

twenty-first. As Nathaniel Wolloch has argued with respect to similarities between

stadial theory and Norbert Elias’s civilizing-process theory, “the similarities

between these two perspectives are much clearer than their differences, and

point to a continuing tradition in modern historiographical interpretations of

the rise of civilization.”^1 For Elias’s theory substitute property theory, and for

historiographical interpretations of the rise of civilization substitute theoretical

interpretations of the rise of private property, and you have my argument.

The significance of this claim lies not only in its implication that modern

commons theory has been somewhat confined by the straits of a discourse

of which it is not even always aware. It lies also in that commons theory’s

portrayals of transitions between property regimes largely partake either

of Enlightenment assumptions of civilizational progress or of a Romantic

reaction to this attitude, with its valorization of the primitive. Thus do deep

cultural attitudes, rooted in the speculative thinking of an earlier age, color

todayʼs theories — positive and normative — of the commons.

To set the stage, consider the concrete examples or allegories used by

commons theorists of the last half century, discussed in Part I. Nearly without

exception, they have skipped over such familiar but prosaic commons as

cooperatives, condominiums, corporations, and neighborhood associations, in

favor of studies of the exotic worlds of hunters, herdsmen, and smallholding

1 Nathaniel Wolloch, The Civilizing Process, Nature, and Stadial Theory , 44 eighTeenTh-cenTury sTud. 245 (2011).

510 Theoretical Inquiries in Law [Vol. 19.2:

attributed the transition between stages to what we might today call increasing

pressure on resources:

The first state of society is that of hunters and fishers; among such a

people the idea of property will be confined to a few, and but a very

few moveables; and subjects which are immoveable, will be esteemed

to be common. In accounts given of many American tribes we read,

that one or two of the tribe will wander five or six hundred miles from

his usual place of abode, plucking the fruit, destroying the game, and

catching the fish throughout the fields and rivers adjoining to all the

tribes which he passes, without any idea of such a property in the

members of them, as makes him guilty of infringing the rights of others.

The next state of society begins, when the inconveniencies and

dangers of such a life, lead men to the discovery of pasturage. During

this period, as soon as a flock have brouzed [sic] upon one spot of

ground, their proprietors will remove them to another; and the place

they have quitted will fall to the next who pleases to take possession

of it: for this reason such shepherds will have no notion of property

in immoveables, nor of right of possession longer than the act of

possession lasts. The words of Abraham to Lot are: “Is not the whole

land before thee? Separate thyself, I pray thee, from me. If thou wilt

take the left hand, then will I go to the right; or if thou depart to the

right hand, then will I go to the left.” And we are told that the reason

of this separation, was, the quantity of flocks, and herds, and tents,

which each of them had, and which the land was unable to support;

and therefore lord [sic] Stairs ingeniously observes, that the parts of

the earth which the patriarchs enjoyed, are termed in the scripture, no

more than the possessions.

A third state of society is produced, when men become so numerous,

that the flesh and milk of their cattle is insufficient for their subsistence,

and when their more extended intercourse with each other, has made them

strike out new arts of life, and particularly the art of agriculture. This

art leading men to bestow thought and labour upon land, increases their

connection with a single portion of it; this connection long continued,

produces an affection; and this affection long continued, together with

the other, produces the notion of property.^5

5 J ohn dalryMPle , an essay Towards a general hisTory of P roPerTy in greaT briTain 86–88 (London, A. Millar 1757). See discussion in sTein, legal evoluTion, supra note 2, at 23–25; M eek, supra note 2, at 99–102.

2018] Savagery, Civilization, and Property 511

The jurist Henry Home, Lord Kames, also connected the stages of society

to property law in his Historical Law Tracts :

In the two first stages of the social life, while men were hunters or

shepherds, there scarce could be any notion of land-property. Men

being strangers to agriculture, and also to the art of building, if it was

not of huts, which could be raised or demolished in a moment, had

no fixed habitations, but wandered about in hordes or clans, in order

to find pasture for their cattle. In this vagrant life men had scarce any

connection with land more than with air or water. A field of grass

might be considered as belonging to a horde or clan, while they were in

possession; and so might the air in which they breathed, and the water

of which they drunk: but the moment they removed to another quarter,

there no longer subsisted any connection betwixt them and the field that

was deserted. It lay open to new-comers, who had the same right as if

it had not been formerly occupied. Hence I conclude, that while men

led the life of shepherds, there was no relation formed betwixt them

and land, in any manner so distinct as to obtain the name of Property.

Agriculture, which makes the third stage of the social life, produced

the relation of land-property. A man who has bestowed labour in preparing

a field for the plough, and who has improved this field by artful culture,

forms in his mind a very intimate connection with it.^6

Elsewhere Kames connected the advance between stages with the pressure

of growing populations on resources:

Plenty of food procured by hunting and fishing, promotes population:

but as consumption of food increases with population, wild animals,

sorely persecuted, become not only more rare, but more shy. Men, thus

pinched for food, are excited to try other means for supplying their

wants. A fawn, a kid, or a lamb, taken alive and tamed for amusement,

suggested probably flocks and herds, and introduced the shepherd-state.

... The shepherd-state is friendly to population. Men by plenty of

food multiply apace.... Necessity, the mother of invention, suggested

agriculture. When corn growing spontaneously was rendered scarce

by consumption, it was an obvious thought to propagate it by art...^7

6 henry hoMe , lord kaMes , hisTorical law T racTs 144–46 (Edinburgh, A. Kincaid & J. Bell, 1758) (footnotes omitted and spelling modernized). See Meek, supra note 2, at 102–07; sTein, legal evoluTion, supra note 2, at 27–28. 7 1 henry hoMe , lord kaMes , skeTches of The hisTory of M an 55–56 (James A. Harris ed., Liberty Fund 2007) (1788). See also id. at 59; 2 id. at 561–

2018] Savagery, Civilization, and Property 513

When the lakes and the forests are exhausted of fish and game, [man]

must seek new means of procuring subsistence....

When the inhabitants are not yet very numerous, they breed cattle,

and become pastors; but when they are greatly multiplied, and are

obliged to find subsistence within a small compass, they must then

cultivate the land, and become agriculturalists....

What follows from the necessity of cultivation?

The necessity of property. 11

This survey of late-Enlightenment stadial thought would not be complete

without William Blackstone, whose influence on modern property theory

might be described as legendary.^12 Blackstone’s account of the development

of private property follows the stadial model developed by his contemporaries

from north of the border:

[W]hile the earth continued bare of inhabitants, it is reasonable to

suppose that all was in common among them, and that every one took

from the public stock to his own use such things as his immediate

necessities required....

But when mankind increased in number, craft, and ambition, it became

necessary to entertain conceptions of more permanent dominion; and

to appropriate to individuals not the immediate use only, but the very

substance of the thing to be used....

Such as were not contented with the spontaneous product of the earth,

sought for a more solid refreshment in the flesh of beasts, which they

obtained by hunting. But the frequent disappointments incident to that

method of provision, induced them to gather together such animals as

were of a more tame and sequacious nature, and to establish a permanent

property in their flocks and herds, in order to sustain themselves in a

less precarious manner....

As the world by degrees grew more populous, it daily became more

difficult to find out new spots to inhabit, without encroaching upon

former occupants: and, by constantly occupying the same individual

spot, the fruits of the earth were consumed, and its spontaneous produce

destroyed, without any provision for future supply or succession. It

therefore became necessary to pursue some regular method of providing

11 2 helvéTius, a TreaTise on Man; his inTellecTual faculTies and his educaTion 424–25 (W. Hooper trans., London, Vernor, Hood & Sharpe 1810) (1773). See also id. at 20, 493; M eek, supra note 2, at 133–34. 12 See David B. Schorr, How Blackstone Became a Blackstonian , 10 TheoreTical inquiries l. 103 (2009).

514 Theoretical Inquiries in Law [Vol. 19.2:

a constant subsistence; and this necessity produced, or at least promoted

and encouraged, the art of agriculture. And the art of agriculture, by a

regular connection and consequence, introduced and established the

idea of a more permanent property in the soil than had hitherto been

received and adopted....

Necessity begat property... 13

It bears noting that while these stadial theories were presented as positive

theories of societal development, in their historical context they typically

made an implicit, normative claim — that property institutions could, and

should, progress to increasingly private property. 14

It also bears noting that opponents of such “progress,” while opposing

the normative tint of the stadial story, stayed firmly within its descriptive

framework. 15 Writers from the Roman Lucretius to the Romantics of the

nineteenth century considered humankind to have evolved through the same

stages as the Scottish thinkers discussed above, but valorized early stages,

with their common property arrangements, holding up the “noble savage” as

an ideal.^16 As Smithʼs contemporary, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, wrote:

So long as men remained content with their rustic huts, so long as

they were satisfied with clothes made of the skins of animals and sewn

together with thorns and fish-bones... they lived free, healthy, honest

and happy lives.... But... from the moment it appeared advantageous

to any one man to have enough provisions for two, equality disappeared,

property was introduced, work became indispensable, and vast forests

became smiling fields, which man had to water with the sweat of his

brow, and where slavery and misery were soon seen to germinate and

grow up with the crops.^17

13 williaM blacksTone, 2 coMMenTaries 3–8. See Meek, supra note 2, at 177–79. 14 rahMaTian, supra note 4, at 144. See also Nathaniel Wolloch, The Idea of Historical Progress in the Transition from Enlightenment Historiography to Classical Political Economy , 9 adaM sMiTh rev. 75, 76 (2016). 15 See Fritz L. Kramer, Eduard Hahn and the End of the “Three Stages of Man , 57 geograPhical rev. 73, 75 (1967). 16 Jean-Jacques rousseau, Discourse: The Second Part , in The social conTracT and discourses 207 (G.D.H. Cole trans., 1923) (1754); George Boas, Primitivism , in 3 dicTionary of The hisTory of ideas 557 (Philip P. Wiener ed., 1973); ThoMas hylland eriksen & finn siverT nielsen, a hisTory of anThroPology 12– (2d ed. 2013); Kramer, supra note 15, at 75, 78. 17 rousseau , supra note 16, at 214–15.

516 Theoretical Inquiries in Law [Vol. 19.2:

First we abandoned the commons in food gathering, enclosing farm

land and restricting pastures and hunting and fishing areas.^22

Approximately contemporaneously with Hardin’s article, Harold Demsetz

published his Toward a Theory of Property Rights. 23 Here the similarities

to stadial theory were yet more prominent. Demsetz, relying on the work

of anthropologists who had studied native tribes of the Canadian northeast,

described societies that had moved from hunting to husbandry of fur-bearing

animals (husbandry being either a sort of pastoralism or agriculture). Demsetz

argued that this change in subsistence methods was accompanied by a change

in property arrangements — lack of private property gave way, as a response

to new, commercial demands for pelts, to defined property rights in land:

We may safely surmise that the advent of the fur trade had two immediate

consequences. First, the value of furs to the Indians was increased

considerably. Second, and as a result, the scale of hunting activity

rose sharply. Both consequences must have increased considerably

the importance of the externalities associated with free hunting. The

property right system began to change, and it changed specifically in

the direction required to take account of the economic effects made

important by the fur trade.^24

While not tracking Enlightenment stadial theory precisely, Demsetz’s account

overlapped with it in several respects (not at all coincidentally, as we will

see): echoes of the progression hunting-pastoralism-agriculture-commerce, an

accompanying shift to increasingly defined property rights, and an explanatory

mechanism based on increasing pressure on the resource. 25 Regarding this last

point, Demsetz’s consideration of externalities was markedly similar to Adam

Smith’s argument that “when flocks and herds come to be reared property

then becomes of a very considerable extent; there are many opportunities of

injuring one another and such injuries are extremely pernicious to the sufferer.”^26

22 Id. at 1248. 23 Harold Demsetz, Toward a Theory of Property Rights , 57 aM. econ. rev. 347 (1967). 24 Id. at 352. 25 See also Armen A. Alchian & Harold Demsetz, The Property Right Paradigm , 33 J. econ. hisT. 16, 19–25 (1973). For an analysis pointing out the similarities between Demsetz’s account and the earlier theories of Locke and Blackstone, see Carol M. Rose, Evolution of Property Rights , in 2 The new Palgrave dicTionary of law and econoMics 93, 94 (1998). 26 sMiTh, supra note 9, at 33–34.

2018] Savagery, Civilization, and Property 517

Demsetz’s work was extremely influential on property theorists in the legal

academy, many of whom continue to make use of the stadial paradigm. James

Krier, for instance, recently advanced a modified Demsetzian account of the

evolution of property rights from hunter-gatherer societies with communal

ownership to agricultural ones with individual ownership. 27 Demsetz’s model

also had major impacts on the economic literature on the commons,^28 as well

as on the “common pool resources” literature associated with Elinor Ostrom.^29

Perhaps less obvious, but in some respects uncannily similar to Adam Smith’s

theory, is Carol Rose’s influential classification of management strategies for

common resources.^30 Rose sets out four “management techniques” — or legal

regimes — that can be used to keep exploitation or use at an efficient level:

In “Do-Nothing” there are no legal controls on use; “Keepout” controls who

is entitled to exploit the resource and who not; “Rightway” prescribes how

users may use or exploit the resource; and “Property” grants individualized

property rights to users. Each is progressively more sophisticated and better

at preventing overuse of the resource, but also more expensive to run, and

so society is best off, Rose argues, in climbing the ladder of legal regimes as

resource congestion increases. Not only is Rose’s model a four-stage theory;

it also tracks Smith’s association of increasing pressure on a resource with

increasingly elaborate legal regimes culminating in private property.^31

Finally, the massive literature on “common property resources” identified

with Elinor Ostrom, the International Association for the Study of the Commons,

and related institutions, seems to borrow from stadial theory in several respects.

The empirical studies in this body of work were carried out primarily with

regard to the (now) exotic worlds of hunters, shepherds, and peasant farmers

about which stadial theorists wrote, not to the more familiar (to most of

us) worlds of common property in urban dwellings, businesses, or cultural

endeavors;^32 a tendency all the more striking in light of Ostrom’s background

27 James E. Krier, Evolutionary Theory and the Origin of Property Rights , 95 cornell l. rev. 139, 157–59 (2009). 28 See for example Terry L. Anderson & P.J. Hill, The Evolution of Property Rights: A Study of the American West , 18 J.l. & econ. 163 (1975) and the literature it spawned. 29 See, e.g. , Bonnie J. McCay & James M. Acheson, Human Ecology of the Commons , in The quesTion of The coMMons 1, 17, 20–21 (Bonnie J. McCay & James M. Acheson eds., 1987) [hereinafter: The quesTion of The coMMons]. 30 Carol M. Rose, Rethinking Environmental Controls: Management Strategies for Common Resources , 40 duke l.J. 1 (1991). 31 See sMiTh, supra note 9. 32 Ostrom’s lead article in the first issue of the International Journal of the Commons identified fishery, forestry, irrigation, water management, and animal husbandry

2018] Savagery, Civilization, and Property 519

light of the specific rules of the particular canal.... The final decisions

of the court are recorded, but not the proceedings.^37

More generally, hundreds of studies on common pool resources in the

Ostromian vein followed, holding up indigenous commons as a model for

sustainable management of resources.^38 As one self-critical member of the

Ostrom school has written,

The idea of the “commons” harkens to a mythic time — before The

Fall or before Capitalism or before The Gods Became Crazy — when

people lived in harmony with each other and with nature and hence there

was no need for the institutions of private property.... The romantic

appeal of “the commons” is doubtless part of the old Western suspicion

that “individualism” is flawed, and that a better way of life could be

found in small rural communities where people shared in common

even the very land upon which they depended.... [R]omanticization

of prestate, preindustrial, pre-Columbian, pre-whatever human society

is central to this narrative.^39

III. F rom stadIal theory to commons theory

The modern commons theorists discussed above did not explicitly refer to the

Enlightenment or Romantic thinkers whose theories may have influenced them.

Yet the striking similarities between these two groups of theories, separated

though they were by two centuries, seem to provide evidence of influence. It

is likely that thinking in terms of civilizational stages was simply so deeply

entrenched in the intellectual baggage of educated Westerners, whether through

study of the classics, of Blackstone, or of Gibbon, that modern commons

37 osTroM, supra note 32, at 71-72 (notes omitted). 38 See Bonnie J. McCay, Community and the Commons: Romantic and Other Views , in coMMuniTies and The environMenT: eThniciTy , gender , and The sTaTe in coMMuniTy - based conservaTion 180, 181 (Arun Agrawal & Clark C. Gibson eds., 2001). Ostrom herself said late in life: “I am deeply indebted to the indigenous peoples in the U.S. who had an image of seven generations being the appropriate time to think about the future. I think we should all reinstate in our mind the seven-generation rule,” Elinor Ostrom, Crafting Rules to Sustain Resources, remarks delivered May 8, 2008, http://www.aapss.org/news/crafting- rules-to-sustain-resources (last visited Feb. 12, 2018). 39 McCay, supra note 38, at 180-81 (citations omitted); See also John R. Wagner, Water and the Commons Imaginary , 53 currenT anThroPology 617, 621 (2012).

520 Theoretical Inquiries in Law [Vol. 19.2:

theorists replicated its patterns as a matter of course. 40 Nevertheless, I suggest

we can also trace more concrete lines of influence through the intertwined

disciplines of anthropology and human ecology, as well as through the worlds

of international development and conservationism.

A. The Aboriginal Property Rights Debate

An important branch of the field of anthropology’s research agenda was largely

set in the mid-nineteenth century by stadial theory, and thereafter developed

to a significant degree in dialogue with it. Anthropological works that clearly

influenced modern commons thought, in particular those cited by Demsetz

in his important 1967 article,^41 were very much part of this dialogue, thereby

infusing his work and that of others writing in the economic tradition with a

large dose of stadial thinking.

The Victorian-era thinkers who strongly influenced anthropology in its

founding era — Henry Maine, Lewis Henry Morgan, Karl Marx, and Friedrich

Engels — were themselves influenced by the stadial theories of the late

eighteenth century, and saw societies as evolving through modes of subsistence

or production, viewed largely through the lens of property.^42 But while Maine

saw the transition from common to private property as a sign of civilization,^43

Morgan, and, following him, Marx and Engels, saw this transition as a form

of injustice and source of inequality (though perhaps a necessary one).

Morgan, based on his knowledge of American Indians and reading of

classical sources, argued that property was a key factor in the evolution

of society as it progressed from a state of savagery (based on hunting) to

barbarism (based on herding and farming) to one of civilization:

40 See Wolloch, supra note 1; M eek, supra note 2, at 2; sTein, Four Stage Theory , supra note 2, at 409. For stadial theory in Gibbon (edward gibbon, The hisTory of The decline and fall of The roMan eMPire (London, William Strahan & Thomas Cadell, 1776)), see M eek, supra note 2, at 175; J.G.A. Pocock, Gibbon and the Shepherds: The Stages of Society in the Decline and Fall , 2 hisT. eur. ideas 193 (1981). 41 Demsetz, supra note 23. 42 See Siomonn Pulla, A Redirection in Neo-Evolutionism?: A Retrospective Examination of the Algonquian Family Hunting Territories Debates , 7 hisT. anThroPology ann. 170 (2011); Chris Hann, Property: Anthropological Aspects , in 19 inTernaTional encycloPedia of The social and behavioral sciences 153 (2d ed. 2015); sTein , legal evoluTion , supra note 2, at 107–11; george w. sTocking , J r., vicTorian anThroPology 11 (1987). 43 henry suMner M aine , ancienT law 237–94 (4th Am. ed., 1906) (1861). See sTein, legal evoluTion, supra note 2, at 107; Hann, supra note 42.

522 Theoretical Inquiries in Law [Vol. 19.2:

their opposing positions, claiming that Speck’s work supported his own account,

while ignoring the normative subtext of Leacock’s so antagonistic to his own.

Speck’s research focused on showing that the native groups of the

northeastern U.S. and Canada had had property from a very early stage,

before contact with Europeans. His work was “whipped into a ‛disproof’

of Morgan, Marx, and Engels by antievolutionists.” 47 At the opening of his

major 1915 article on the subject, he explained what was at stake in terms of

evolutionary theories of property and society:

The idea has always prevailed, without bringing forth much criticism,

that, in harmony with other primitive phenomena, the American Indians

had little or no interest in the matter of claims and boundaries to the

land which they inhabited. This notion has, in fact, been generally

presupposed for all native tribes who have followed a hunting life, to

accord with the common impression that a hunter has to range far, and

wherever he may, to find game enough to support his family.

Whether or not the hunting peoples of other continents, or even of

other parts of America, have definite concepts regarding individual or

group ownership of territory, I should at least like to show that the Indian

tribes of eastern and northern North America did have quite definite

claims to their habitat. Moreover, as we shall see, these claims existed

even within the family groups composing the tribal communities....

It would seem, then, that such features characterize actual ownership

of territory. 48

In later articles, Speck and his supporters explicitly argued for the

aboriginality of property in hunting territories, rejecting the thesis that these

47 J erry d. M oore , visions of culTure : an inTroducTion To anThroPological T heories and T heorisTs 219 (3d ed., 2009). See Frank G. Speck & Loren C. Eiseley, Montagnais-Naskapi Bands and Family Hunting Districts of the Central and Southeastern Labrador Peninsula , 85 Proc. aM. Phil. soc’y 215, 238 (1942); Richard B. Lee & Richard H. Daly, Eleanor Leacock, Labrador, and the Politics of Gatherer-Hunters , in froM labrador To saMoa : The Theory and P racTice of eleanor burke leacock 33, 34 (Constance R. Sutton ed., 1993); Christine Ward Gailey, Eleanor Burke Leacock (1922–1987) , in woMen anThroPologisTs: selecTed biograPhies 215, 217 (Ute Gacs, Aisha Khan, Jerrie McIntyre & Ruth Weinberg, eds., 1989). 48 Frank G. Speck, The Family Hunting Band as the Basis of Algonkian Social Organization , 17 aM. anThroPologisT (n.s.) 289 (1915); Frank G. Speck, The Basis of American Indian Ownership of Land , old P enn weekly rev., Jan. 16, 1915, at 491, version cited in Demsetz, supra note 23, at 351.

2018] Savagery, Civilization, and Property 523

developed only in response to the increased demand for beaver pelts spurred

by European traders.^49

Speck’s position was thus actually diametrically opposed to that of Demsetz,

who argued that the aboriginal peoples of northeast Canada developed private

property in land only in response to the increasing value of hunting brought

about by contact with European traders who placed high values on furs. 50

Whether or not Demsetz realized that Speck’s position contradicted his own,

it is clear that Demsetz was reading anthropological literature deeply engaged

with stadial theory.

Leacock’s work, on the other hand, actually did support Demsetz’s position

that property rights had developed among the native peoples of the Northeast

as a response to increased pressure on the fur resources brought about by

colonial trade. Leacock was firmly in the evolutionist camp of anthropology,^51

and believed that it was only colonialism that had led to private property in

trapping grounds.^52 A Marxist feminist, her work on the natives of Labrador —

work that she herself described as “polemic” — was directed against Speck’s

anti-Marxist theses and dedicated to showing that communism had existed

in this society before it was corrupted by colonialist commerce into adopting

private property.^53 She advanced an evolutionary, three-stage model of society

à la Morgan and Engels, with property regimes deteriorating from primitive

communism to capitalist private property.^54 But the work cited by Demsetz

was published in the 1950s, when Leacock hid her Marxism.^55 We thus have

the tasty irony of Demsetz, a director of the libertarian Mont Pelerin Society,

basing his classic article on the work that was (probably unknown to him)

49 See, e.g. , Frank G. Speck & Loren C. Eiseley, Significance of Hunting Territory Systems of the Algonkian in Social Theory , 41 aM. anThroPologisT (n.s.) 269 (1939); John M. Cooper, Is the Algonquian Family Hunting Ground System Pre-Columbian? , 41 aM. anThroPologisT (n.s.) 66 (1939). 50 Demsetz, supra note 23, at 351–53. 51 See, e.g. , Eleanor Leacock, Introduction to Social Stratification and Evolutionary Theory: A Symposium , 5 eThnohisTory 193 (1958). 52 Eleanor Leacock, The Montagnais “Hunting Territory” and the Fur Trade , 56 aM. anThroPologisT (Pt. 2), Memoir No. 78 (1950). 53 Eleanor Burke Leacock, Introduction , in frederick engels, origin of The faMily, P rivaTe P roPerTy and The sTaTe 1, 7, 19 (1972); Eleanor Burke Leacock, Being an Anthropologist , in froM labrador To saMoa, supra note 47, at 19. See Pulla, supra note 42, at 184–85. 54 See Eleanor B. Leacock, Lewis Henry Morgan on Government and Property , in new direcTions in P oliTical econoMy : an aPProach froM anThroPology 307 (Madeline B. Léons & Frances Rothstein eds., 1979). 55 See M oore , supra note 47, at 221.

2018] Savagery, Civilization, and Property 525

The staff of Hailey’s African Survey seem to have created something of

a nexus for stadial thought in the context of colonial development. London

School of Economics anthropologist Lucy Mair’s chapter on land made

heavy use of the stadial framework for considering “the evolution of the most

suitable form of land tenure”:^60

In some areas land custom is changing rapidly under the influence of

new conditions, such as the increase of the pressure of population or

the spread of a market economy. These changes will eventually involve

official intervention... ; the need must, for example, be envisaged for

the definition and recording of title...^61

There is nothing peculiar to Africa in the general direction which

the evolution of land custom is taking; its adjustment in response to

economic changes is a natural process which would occur independently

of any action taken by the administration.^62

In Mair’s analysis, traditional, communal forms of African land tenure

needed to progress to more private rights in order to encourage development:

All discussions on the subject agree as to the value of giving security

to the occupier of land, and the further advantage of what is generally

termed the individualization of tenures. It has been urged on different

occasions that the extended system of rights, vested in the family or

group, has proved in Africa to be an obstacle to improved agriculture. 63

Strikingly, Mair also reported on Hardin’s tragedy of the commons, avant

la lettre , herdsman and all:

Those who have had to deal with East African conditions have added

the... argument that there is little incentive to natives to reduce their

live-stock in order to prevent the wastage of pasture and consequent

erosion, since nothing done by the individual will avail unless his

neighbours take corresponding action....^64

David Mills, British Anthropology at the End of Empire: The Rise and Fall of the Colonial Social Science Research Council, 1944–1962 , 6 revue d’hisToire des sciences huMaines 161, 163–68 (2002). 60 hailey, supra note 59, at 864. For Mair’s authorship of this chapter, see Cell, Lord Hailey , supra note 59, at 498. 61 hailey, supra note 59, at 830. See also id. at 842. 62 Id. at 865. 63 Id. at 868–69. See also id. at 863–64. 64 Id. at 869.

526 Theoretical Inquiries in Law [Vol. 19.2:

Moreover, in a remarkable anticipation of later legal scholarship that

highlighted potential “comedies of the commons” and “tragedies” of its

disappearance,^65 she also warned of the advantages of common property in

some situations: “The question of rights over grazing commonages presents

its own difficulties; the partition of grazing grounds into small units would

be a bar to the adoption of that rotational use of pasture which many hold to

be the best preventive of erosion in East African conditions.”^66

Anthropologist Charles Kingsley Meek’s 1946 Land Law and Custom in the

Colonies , a study initiated by Hailey’s committee, opened with an argument

that increasing population required rigid rules of land tenure. 67 Lord Hailey

himself contributed an introduction to the volume, in which he laid out a stadial

framework for understanding changes in land tenure in the context of colonial

development, apparently heavily reliant on Mair’s chapter for the African

Survey. The transition between “stages of development” — from a pastoral

economy to subsistence agriculture and then to market-oriented production

— is accompanied, he wrote, by “automatic” changes in the system of land

tenure, with a growing conception of individual ownership. 68 “A further stage

arrives when, with the growing density of population and increased pressure

on the land, holdings acquire a transferable value, and rights in them become

more completely commercialized.”^69

In the normative dimension, Hailey generally approved of this evolution

of property rights on efficiency grounds:

In the extensive Colonial areas in which the system of landholding

is based on the conception of a collective right in the land, the most

conspicuous effect of economic development will... appear in the

progressive individualization of holdings. That process will have the

economic advantage of giving to the holders a greater sense of security

and a greater incentive to a more intensive type of cultivation...^70

But, building on Mair’s insight, Hailey also warned of potentially deleterious

effects of private property:

65 See Carol Rose, The Comedy of the Commons: Custom, Commerce, and Inherently Public Property , 53 U. chi. l. rev. 711 (1986); Michael A. Heller, The Tragedy of the Anticommons: Property in the Transition from Marx to Markets , 111 harv. l. rev. 621 (1998). 66 hailey, supra note 59, at 870. 67 C.K. M eek, land law and cusToM in The colonies vi, 1 (1946). 68 Lord Hailey, Introduction by Lord Hailey , in M eek, supra note 67, at xii–xiii. 69 Id. at xii. 70 Id. at xix.