






Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Prepare for your exams
Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points to download
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Community
Ask the community for help and clear up your study doubts
Discover the best universities in your country according to Docsity users
Free resources
Download our free guides on studying techniques, anxiety management strategies, and thesis advice from Docsity tutors
The upshot is that justice is explained by the principle of utility, but as applied to general rules rather than acts. However, Mill still says that the rules ...
Typology: Study Guides, Projects, Research
1 / 12
This page cannot be seen from the preview
Don't miss anything!
Responses to misunderstandings ^ of hedonism:^ ^ pleasure an aim worthy of swine (pp. 55ff.). Higher, distinctively human,pleasures outweigh mere bodily pleasures shared with swine.^ ^ happiness an inappropriate aim (pp. 59ff.). The aim isn’t ecstasy but just tominimize pain and achieve a comfortable mix of pleasures. Total happiness, notjust one’s own, is the standard of right action (vs. motive of the virtuous agent). ^ of utilitarianism [“proper”]:^ ^ leaves no room for beauty, ornament, amusement (p. 54). popular misconception^ ^ a “godless” doctrine (p. 68). Spells out what a benevolent God would want.^ ^ undercuts “principled” adherence to rules (pp. 68ff.): Rule-breaking is almostalways forbidden because of harmful side-effects. Established rules sum up thegeneral tendencies of acts to promote utility. We should limit direct appeal to theprinciple of utility to cases where the rules conflict.
part^ of the act being judged – what one is tryingto do -- not a further aim the one hopes to achieve by doing it, i.e. amotive.
ingredients^ of happiness.
Twentieth-century objections ^ to hedonism^ ^ from interpersonal comparisons: It’s impossible to measure oneperson’s pleasure or pain against another’s.^ ^ from objective good: We also care about whether our pleasurableexperiences correspond to reality (Nozick’s “experience machine”). ^ to utilitarianism [“proper”]^ ^ from justice: Utilitarianism allows for “interpersonal trade-offs,” or thesacrifice of some to the total good (cf., e.g., trolley cases, “telishment,”distribution of wealth).^ ^ from moral emotion: Utilitarianism would involve too much detachmentfrom emotions essential to moral agency (Williams on “integrity”).
Moral wrong ^ Mill argues that our sense of justice, which is based on the primitiveurge to retaliate for harm, depends for its content and “binding”moral status on utilitarianism. ^ His initial review of the types of things that count as unjust, alongwith etymology, reveals that they have in common reference toviolation of a law, real or ideal. But it also brings out conflictinginterpretations. ^ He notes that an act is
morally wrong^ (= a violation of moralobligation, or duty) only if it deserves punishment, at least by socialdisapproval or conscience. ^ So some acts that fail to maximize the good may not really be wrongbut just “inexpedient” – in the broader sense in which Mill uses theterm here [as “non-optimal” = not the best].
rights.