











Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Prepare for your exams
Study with the several resources on Docsity
Earn points to download
Earn points by helping other students or get them with a premium plan
Community
Ask the community for help and clear up your study doubts
Discover the best universities in your country according to Docsity users
Free resources
Download our free guides on studying techniques, anxiety management strategies, and thesis advice from Docsity tutors
In this paper, Edwin Coleman argues against the common belief that there is a fallacy of arguing from authority. He challenges the 'part-time fallacy' and examines the weaknesses in the literature that supports the existence of such a fallacy. Coleman suggests that bad arguments which appeal to authority are defective through breach of felicity conditions on argument as a speech act, rather than through employing a bad principle of inference.
What you will learn
Typology: Study notes
1 / 19
This page cannot be seen from the preview
Don't miss anything!
EDWIN COLEMAN University of Melbourne
Keywords: fallacy, argument, authority, speech act. Abstract: I argue that there is no fallacy of argument from authority. I first show the weakness of the case for there being such a fallacy: text-book presentations are confused, alleged examples are not genuinely exemplary, reasons given for its alleged fallaciousness are not convincing. Then I analyse arguing from authority as a complex speech act. R~iecting the popular but unjustified category of the "part-time fallacy", I show that bad arguments which appeal to authority are defective through breach of some felicity condition on argument as a speech act, not through employing a bad principle of inference.
There's never been a satisfactory theory of fallacy, as Hamblin pointed out in his book of 1970, in what is still the least unsatisfactory discussion. Things have not much improved in the last 25 years, despite fallacies getting more attention as interest in informal logic has grown. We still lack good answers to simple questions like what is a fallacy?, what fallacies are there? and how should we classifY fallacies?
The idea that argument from authority (argumentum ad verecundiam) is a fallacy, is well-established in logical tradition. I argue that it is no such thing. The second main part of the paper is negative: I show the weakness of the case made in the literature for there being such a fallacy as argument from authority. First, text-book presentation of the fallacy is confused, second, the examples given are not genuinely exemplary and third, reasons given for its alleged fallaciousness are not convincing. Fourth, attempts to improve on the text-book accounts in recent literature are not much help. The third main part is positive: I propose that consideration of arguing from authority as a complex speech act illuminates existing discussion and points toward a clear and simple positive argument for there being no such fallacy. Specifically, I suggest that such an analysis enables us to reject the unjustified category of the "part-time fallacy" (which has increasingly shown up in texts recently), by showing that bad arguments which appeal to authority are defective through breach of some felicity condition on argument as a speech act rather than through employing a bad principle of inference. The variety of ways such an argument can go wrong reflects the complex structure of felicity conditions on it, not a long and unprincipled list of unexpressed premises, as some authors have argued. Arguing from authority uses a good principle of inference: after all, some arguments of this kind are good. There is no fallacy of argument from authority.
366 Edwin Coleman
It is commonly said that argument from authority is a fallacy, and a fallacy is generally said to be a type of argument which seems good but is notl. Now an argument (in this sense) can be bad in two ways, through having a false or unacceptable premise or through having a bad inference. Many logicians put aside the unacceptable premises with the sense of 'fallacy' as a false belief, emphasising logic's concern with inference. It is having a defective inference that makes a fallacy bad; it is a bad type of argument. To say that the inference of an argument is bad is to say that the premises give no support to the conclusion. So a fallacy is a type of argument whose premises, even if true, give no support to the conclusion, though they may seem to. (Some informal logicians do want to treat false premises as sources of fallacy, and I will discuss some below; I think this is a mistake and give some argument against it, but this paper is mainly intended to counter the idea that arguing from authority is a fallacy in the narrower sense just given.)
The argument from authority is this kind of argument: Aristotle says that the earth does not move. so the earth does not move. But this form A says p. so p
is not worth using instead of the plain assertion p unless challenges like 'who's A?' or 'how would A know?' can be met with a response giving some kind of credential to A. So I think it is reasonable to say that this form is enthymematic, that there is a standard omitted premise and that the form of the argument should be taken as A says p. A is authoritative on sllch things. so p These days expertise is as often taken as authority so we may also put it E says p. E is expert on p. so p
raj Confused Presentation
Most authors these days grant that some appeals to authority are legitimate, which may seem to suggest that I am beating on an open door: few current authors are so incautious as to claim that there is a fallacy of arguing from authority simpliciter. However things are not so simple. Writers on fallacy still mostly manage to convey the message that argument from authority is a bad thing.
Older logic books unabashedly declare there is a fallacy of argumentum ad verecundiam, or appealing to authority; but judging from their ways of presenting their discussions, it seems that many authors are rather uncertain that there really is a fallacy. The better recent books tend to imply that there is such a fallacy by their section headings but to say in their discussion that appealing to authority is "sometimes a fallacy." The notion of a part-time fallacy is not much discussed, but some have marked this shift by referring instead to the fallacy of appealing to
368 Edwin Coleman
claim 'everything Jim Jones says is so' this was simply making a false claim. It cannot be the type of argument that wipes out all other considerations but rather the blame is on the participants' attitudes to Jones, to arguments etc. Fallacy is not necessarily involved just because irrationality is. So, if the type of argument intended here is characterised by a premise of the kind 'everything X says is so' its fault is just having a false premise; but if the fault adverted to is blind faith, that is no fallacy either. [2] "Irrelevant expertise. When the appeal is to an authority whose expertise is in some field other than the one at issue, the appeal is to irrelevant expertise. For example, quoting the political or economic opinions of a distinguished physicist like Oppenheimer or Einstein is fallacious because the massive weight of an Einstein's opinion in the field of physics may not transfer to other fields." Here again the problem is a simple mistaken belief-that Einstein is authoritative about politics; not a mistaken inference of appealing to authority. (Incidentally to say that Einstein's views about politics should not be given weight just because he is an expert on physics, clearly presupposes that appeal to a genuine authority is fine.) [3] The third kind of example they give is so-called testimonials, for example: Don Meredith for Lipton's tea: "What makes me a Lipton's tea lover? Lipton tastes so damn good." As it stands, there is no argument here, so no fallacy. To invent an argument equivalent to the ad we might try something like You should drink Lipton:s tea, because Don Meredith says it:~ good and we will have to impute to the advertisers
Thus the idea is that the ad is equivalent to the argument Lipton S tea lastes good to Don Meredith /flea tastes good 10 Don Meredith it will laste good to you, so You should drink Lipton s lea The artificiality and lack of real equivalence of the result is obvious. It derives from trying to find in the ad an attempt to prove something, as though the advertisers want to prove that Lipton's tea is good, and offer as evidence Don's statement. But an ad is not an attempt at proof; this one is really urging:
Be like Don Meredith, drink Lipton s tea. If Don Meredith, whoever he is, says Lipton's tea tastes good to him, then if true, this might be a good reason for my drinking it if I want to ape him, or might not, if I don't. Most likely it's simply a lie. If there is something wrong here it is it is his lying or the advertisers' wrongly thinking I want to ape him, not a mistaken inference. Nobody believes the imputed premise and there is no reason to impute it because there is not even an attempt at argument, so how can there be a fallacy? [4] "Unidentified experts. Frequently expert opinion is merely alluded to, or is identified in such a vague or incomplete way that its reliability, accuracy, and weight are impossible to verify... phrases like "experts agree"." The example they give is
Doctors recommend one pain reliever most: the one you get in Anacin.
This is a pretty bad example because the main thing wrong here is the misleading implication that the pain reliever in question, namely aspirin, is only found in Anacin. If we remove this distraction we get Doctors recommend one pain reliever most: Anacin. This is no longer a real example and probably no longer true, but never mind: is it a fallacy? It is not yet an argument, so let's make it one: Doctors recommend one pain reliever most: Anacin. So Anacin is best. Now this is certainly not a very good argument for the very simple reason that the term 'doctors' is too vague. But Most physicians recommend one pain reliever most: Anacin. So Anacin is best. would be a (fairly) good argument if the premise were true, and it isn't good just because that premise is false. On the other hand Most physicians recommend one pain reliever most: aspirin. So aspirin is best. is not an argument for the conClusion wanted although it is an acceptable though weak argument from authority. But even then it is weak because we have 'most physicians' not' 'all physicians'. Neither version is bad because it appeals to authority. [5] "Experts with axes to grind. Sometimes claims are advanced by appeal to experts who do have impressive and genuinely relevant credentials. but whose testimony may legitimately be suspected due to demonstrable conflict of interest ... Suppose our attention is directed to an inconclusive study of the effects of second-hand tobacco smoke conducted at a reputable institution under the direction of someone with genuine scientific credentials. Now suppose we learn that the study was underwritten by a research grant supplied by the Tobacco Institute. We should at least look for other studies to compare this one with." I agree entirely with the conclusion here. Only I don't see what fallacy is being alluded to. Incidentally it is noteworthy that discussions of this "fallacy" generally go in for these vague descriptions rather than concrete examples. Presumably the idea intended here is that someone might say Expert E says passive smoking is harmless. so passive smoking is harmless
where E is the recipient of the dubious funding. (Of course, no-one would actually say E says smoking is harmless and E is an expert but E has ajinancial interest in people believing smoking is harmless, so smoking is harmless.
If the third premise is left out the argument might well be contested by pointing it out; but that shows that it is part of the opposite case not of this argument.) But there may well be nothing wrong with an argument of this kind even when such a clause is true: most proponents of theories have an interest in other people believing them, even physicists. We don't ignore Einstein's views in physics because it was to his advantage to become a widely respected physicist.
If there is something wrong with the argument it must boil down to the fact
[cl Arguments Given for Fallaciousness are Poor
372 Edwin Coleman
simply confuses the knowledge of the fact and the knowledge of the reasoned fact, as Aristotle puts it. That some authority accepts a fact is a good, though defeasible reason to believe it; but it does not of course explain why it is so. p is rarely correct as a result of E's thinking it so. Other reasons for believing p might make plain why it is so, but this does not mean that authority cannot show it to be so. What "arguing [p, since E accepts pJ" means is never "p, merely because E accepts p" so Salmon is engaging in travesty to report this form of argument in these terms. These attempts to argue that appealing to authority is irrational are not very convincing ways to show that it is a fallacy. The other main argument is commonly implied in the course of discussion of examples: the fact is that such arguments are not conclusive: the desired conclusion could be false even though the premises are true. Despite what authors say a fallacy is, this tends to become the test for it. This "test" is applied to examples of other alleged fallacies too; and if one examines what is said about other fallacies one finds that quite a few are also claimed to be only sometimes fallacious, and that the examples given of other alleged fallacies are also frequently not even arguments, not bad arguments, or if bad are bad for reasons other than the one alleged. This all suggests that it is important to examine what exactly a fallacy is said, in general, to be. I will not go into this matter here because there is a long and complicated historical story to be told; although this is particularly relevant to explaining why and when it has been claimed that there is a fallacy of arguing from authority - since, and consequent on, the successful struggle of science to wrest intellectual authority from the Church - in this paper I confine myself to arguing that there is no such fallacy. I will take up these related issues on another occasion.
[d] The Enthymeme Approach is Unprincipled
Since all accounts agree at some point that not every argument from authority is fallacious, let us return to the idea of a part-time fallacy. In the journal literature some attempt has been made to determine when an argument of this kind is acceptable and when not, by identifying implicit premises for the "true form" of this type of argument, any of whose breach can lead to a "fallacious" use. The idea of treating argument from authority as an enthymeme is a natural one as I said at the beginning. A saysp, sop
is commonly cited. though the real form of the argument is A says p, A is authoritative on such things, so p. But I want to contrast this recognition of a commonly suppressed premise with a strategy followed by some writers, for example Woods and Walton [1979a,b], which I think is misguided. It consists in attempting to identify a list of conditions which must be met if argument from authority is to be good, and building them into the form of the argument as further suppressed premises. The idea is that the real form of argument from authority is something like
374 Edwin Coleman
[eJ Walton 1989
Walton's discussion of argument from authority in [1989b] seems to me to improve on his earlier enthymematic approach. He discusses examples of the various kind of flaws which argument from authority can have some of which we have already seen: the Einstein syndrome, the lack of citation, the advertising testimonial, the conflict of experts, interpreting what they say. He refrains in most cases from saying that a fallacy is committed, and avoids talking about "varieties of a fallacy," as Barry and Rudinow do. Rather he proposes a list of questions to ask (rather like Ennis's) and writes of questioning an argument, giving it little weight and so on, rather than dubbing it a fallacy. This general idea of "argument criticisms" rather than fallacies is the right direction to go. However Walton still wants there to be fallacy of arguing from authority, and it is interesting to see how he finds one. He has taken up from Hamblin's historical discussion the need to go back to Locke, and asserts in his introductory remarks that "Locke did not claim that all appeals to authority in argumentation are fallacious" [1989: 173]. Locke called appeal to authority argumentum ad verecundiam (appeal to shame) because he was indeed concerned with intimidatory tactics in debate. Walton now identifies the fallacy in argument from authority as trying to use an appeal to authority to silence opposition. J have three objections to this move. First, in point of fact Locke did not just not claim that not all arguments from authority are fallacious; he didn't claim that any were fallacious. He does not use the term fallacy in the relevant passage at alL Walton is being at least misleading in suggesting that he does. Second, in order to call a fallacy the practice which he has in mind, Walton defines fallacy [1989b: 19] as "important kinds of error or deceptive tactics of argumentation." As far as J know such a dichotomous definition is peculiar to Walton, although it is related to that of van Eemeren and Grootendorst (which I discuss next), through the notion of argumentation as reasoned dialogue. I am not suggesting that we do not want systematic discussion of deceptive tactics in argumentation, we do; but it seems to me very odd to describe the tactic in question as a fallacy. The attempts to cow the opposition in the examples given by Locke and the Port-Royal Logic, like He is of high birth, therefore what he advances is true rely at least as much on prestige, wealth, social position and in general political authority (which Walton wrongly dismisses as irrelevant [1989: 174)), as they do on alleged cognitive authority. One can criticize someone who acts so for hectoring or browbeating or even, though I'd prefer not to use this myself, for sophistry. But fallacy is surely at minimum some kind of error. If not, why doesn't Walton want to call all the other kinds of criticizability of arguments fallacies too? Finally, someone who tries to cow the opposition may well not be trying to or succeeding in deceiving them at all. The various churchmen who cited the authority of Aristotle and the Bible to Galileo were not trying to deceive him but to shut him up.
These authors have tried to conceptualise "argumentative discussions" as dialogues consisting of various specifiable kinds of speech act organised in a specifiable way into a complex structure. They give a lengthy list of rules ideally governing such discussions (seventeen, most with subclauses) and in a bold stroke propose to replace the traditional mess about fallacies by declaring that a fallacy is any breach of any of these rules governing reasoned dialogue. This proposal has two great merits: it recognizes that many flaws in arguments are not really in them but in their context, and it recognizes that argument flaws come in many different kinds. I have a number of reservations about their overall scheme which I will discuss on another occasion (Coleman, forthcoming) because their approach is complex and subtle. All that I want to argue here is that this characterization of fallacy as a breach of a rule of reasoned dialogue is of little help for our present problem. In their [1987], which introduces a slightly different formulation of what the rules of rational discussion are, arguing from authority is simply declared to be an inappropriate method of argumentation, which therefore breaches a rule banning such methods. But I don't think that this will do, since it doesn't allow for the generally accepted fact that there are good cases of such argument. Further, unsuitability is a rather vague property which would need to be made considerably more specific to discriminate among appeals to authority and to explain why some are unacceptable.
I suggest that a speech act analysis of arguing by appeal to authority might be more systematic than the extant discussions. Such an analysis will make plain two dimensions of systematicity in the variety of ways in which argument from authority can go wrong without being fallacious, some of which we have seen in the examples discussed above. Argument from authority is a doubly complex speech act because on the one hand it involves its utterer in arguing, which is itself already a complex speech act, and second because it involves the utterer in reporting someone else's attestation, which is a kind of indirect speech act (indirect in the sense of indirect or reported speech, not the sense in which Searle writes of indirect speech acts4.)
Here is my suggestion. First, to argue is already a complex speech act:
another global set for the whole act of argument. So there are thirty-six ways, not all equally important no doubt, in which the speech act of argument from authority might go wrong. And each of these will itself be possible in various ways. None of them deserves to be called committing a fallacy, but fortunately in order to see that we shall not need to look at all thirty-six of them in detail. Instead I shall argue in turn for some simple consequences of argument from authority's being a speech act, of its being a complex speech act, and of its being a speech act of argument.
The prevalent uncertainty about the role of deception in fallacy seems to me to have a rather simple explanation. If we think of an argument as a speech act and not as a mere propositional structure then there can be an uncertainty as to whether it is W or R or both that is mistaken when a fallacy is committed. The result of abstracting from dialectical contexts is to remove any possibility of anyone being deceived other than a transcendental ego contemplating a propositional structure. Of course, this point has been made before in other ways by various writers urging a dialectical analysis of argument. The speech act perspective provides two further illuminations of the extant discussions of argument from authority. First, it is general feature of speech acts that they presuppose such things as sincerity as part of condition n. Not all do of course, but assertion and attestation do. There is no reason whatever to single out citing an expert with an axe to grind as committing a variety of a fallacy; if the cited expert was not sincere in attesting to p then that attestation is infelicitous and inevitably the complex speech act of which it forms a part will be too. But even if this attestation were not put to use in argument, it would still be flawed by insincerity and just this flaw could be pointed out anyway. A fallacy is surely a flaw in arguing; a flaw which can occur even when one is not arguing should not be called a fallacy even when one is. Or perhaps better, before I am accused of a fallacy myself, I should say that when we say that a fallacy is a flaw in arguing we ought to mean a flaw which is a flaw in the arguing per se. Otherwise we shall have to start counting stuttering and muttering as fallacies, too.
Again, the requirements that the procedure for argument from authority be carried out completely and correctly are general requirements on speech acts, conditions Bland B2. So citing authorities too vaguely to enable checking up-a commonly claimed "variety" or "way" of committing the "fallacy" of arguing from authority-is just a particular form which breaching these requirements can take for this particular speech act. The same point applies here too, that we should not be calling a fallacy what may be a flaw in arguing but which can equally be just a tlaw in an assertion--or even a curse or an apology.
Let us now consider some implications of the complexity of argument from authority as a speech act.
The first is that the textbook obsession with so-called "testimonials"-well- known people praising products in advertisements-actually confuses two different speech acts. Testimony (see Coady 1992) is not appeal to authority at all, it is an exercise of authority: in argument from authority, W makes use of a prior testimony by E, someone different. Don Meredith may be arguing if he is offering viewers reasons to buy tea-bags in his ads for them but he is not arguing by appeal to authority since it would have to be his own authority he would be appealing to. To speak authoritatively is not the same thing as the appeal to authority-it could not be since the point of appealing to authority is to back up what you say with what someone weightier says.
Second, there are many possible flaws in argument from authority not remarked on in textbooks. For example if I claim I am very wise. I say so, and I am expert on myself
then if the second premise is true then I am speaking authoritatively but I am not appealing to authority. I am not usually entitled to appeal to myself as authority (pains being, controversially, a possible exception). Many other novel ways to botch appealing to authority can be devised.
Third, the various different so-called varieties of the fallacies of argument from authority, and problems about the use of experts discussed in the literature, can be systematically attributed to failures of the various conditions on the various constituent speech acts. We have already seen how breach of the fifth condition through insincerity can. invalidate the cited expert attestation and vitiate the argument. Recall that in every speech act, one of the felicity conditions (A2) is that the participants must be appropriately entitled to take their roles for example not just you or I can conduct a wedding or launch a ship. This applies equally to the assertions by W of E's expertise and E's having attested to p. Consider first the question when W is entitled to assert that E attests to p.
First, W must be able to back this claim up, so must have available what we might call a citatory trail. W must be able to supply potential objectors with means to verify that E did indeed attest to p. This in turn typically presupposes the existence of writing, archives, bibliographical conventions and a whole social infrastructure organised around the practice of serious public depositions such as Aristotle's and Einstein's works. Although argument from authority is used in the court situation using verbal testimony from authorities, this is not the typical situation. Rather, typically argument from authority involves citation of published statements. (In any case court records are kept to overcome this difference.)
A second implication of the entitlement requirement, or perhaps of the proper execution requirement (8 I) depending on the case, is that W should not be
E are problems with the premises and cannot be the source of fallacy (though they can be and often are the source of other ways of going wrong).
W argues for p to R if
[ii] W asserts to R that p;
[q may be several premises]
[iii] W indicates to R that q is reason to accept p. Indication is a speech act which is in general less explicit than is assertion. In many of its uses its point depends on its being less than fully explicit (here I part company with Searle's expressibility principle). However this is not the case in argument, where within reason the more explicit the logical signposting the better: to say 'q, so p' is clearer and generally better than a mere 'q;p', though many arguments are given without explicit warranting connectives. So I will amend this account for present purposes and replace clause [iii] with [iii*] W asserts to R that q is reason to accept p with the caveat that what counts as assertion must be interpreted reasonably charitably here. Felicity conditions for arguing are then: [II] The assertion of the premises must be felicitous. [12] The indication or assertion of the support-claim must be felicitous. [13] The assertion of the conclusion must be felicitous.
We have two constituent acts which can go wrong independently corresponding to the usual distinction between arguments with bad premises and those with bad inferences. And there is a third possibility because the speech act of argument is a complex one constituted by the (at least) two assertions: it is not simply a sequence of assertions.
infelicitous is ungrounded-the premises are unacceptable in some way, not necessarily through falsity. [12 flaws] An argument in which the indication of support goes awry mayor may not be a non sequitur. But even a non sequitur is not yet a fallacy, so we need to consider just what felicity condition's failure might make flawed support- indication into a fallacy. Let us leave aside for the moment contexts in which indicating support is not a socially recognised practice (failure of felicity condition A I); in any case one would hardly speak of fallacy then. Perhaps we can see circumstances in which A2 might fail, a participant's not being entitled to make indications, for example witnesses are just supposed to answer questions
There is no Fallacy ofArguingfrom Authority 381
over-eagerness. Failing to carry out the procedure of indication properly or completely (B I or B2) may well make the argument weak because the audience is not clear exactly what the argument is. But this is still not even a nonsequitur. Finally we come to the possibility that the participants' attitudes or actions are inappropriate and it is only here that the possibility of fallacy may arise. Only if W is mistaken in believing that the premises offer support for the conclusion do we have a nonsequitur and possibly a fallacy. [13 flaws] Interestingly, there is a second way in which a fallacy might possibly arise, namely by defective assertion of the conclusion. For example, if there is some difference between the premises asserted and those believed by W to give the conclusion support. Asserting a conclusion is not just asserting some claim, but a claim as a conclusion. We have then two candidates for the fallacy of arguing by appeal to authority: mistakenly believing that the premises support the conclusion, and confusing the issue somehow between premises and conclusion. This latter will be some classical fallacy such as irrelevant conclusion or equivocation-and thus not that other alleged fallacy, appealing to authority. So we are reduced to asking ifthere is a mistake which consists in believing [*J that the premises [E allests to p and E is expertfor p} if true give support to the conclusion p. And the answer is simply no, because virtually everyone admits that sometimes argument from authority is a good argument. Consider for example the kind of argument allegedly put to Galileo: Aristotle says that the earth does not move, so the earth does not move. The argument which was actually used in the Galileo affair and related disputes is actually much better represented as The Bible says that the earth does not move, so the earth does not move. which is enthymematic for The Bible says the earth does not move and the Bible is the 1V0rd of God, so the earth does not move and this in turn seems to have been taken as equivalent to God says the earth does not move. so the earth does not move This argument must surely be good: what better reason could one have for accepting p than God's asserting it? Of course. the truth of the premise presupposes the existence of God with the usual Christian properties, but if it is true it is surely completely unthinkable that the earth does not move should be false and that this should not be a good argument for it.
attests 10 p and E is expert jor p} is true then it does give support to p. Those premises, if true, do give support to that conclusion. I do not claim that they show it to be true, only that they support it: they give one good reason to believe it. Arguing from authority is not a conclusive form of argument. Of course, the premises only give any support to the conclusion if they are true; but this is equally true for demonstrative arguments like,
There is no Fallacy ofArguingfrom Authority 383
felicity: we really need to develop an account of "speech" acts which takes documentation seriously. This is a large task.
References
Austin J [1972] How to do things with words Oxford: Oxford University Press. Barry V and Rudinow J [1989] Invitation to critical thinking Fort Worth: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. Cederblom J and Paulsen W [1988J "Making reasonable decisions in world of experts" in Govier [1988]. Coady [1992] Testimony Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Proceedings, Fourth National Reasoning Conference, Sydney: UTS. Coleman E [1997] "Fallacies: there are and there aren't" forthcoming. Copi I [1961] Introduction to logic. 2 nd^ ed. New York: Macmillan. Copi I {and C Cohen} [1990] Introduction to logic, S'h ed. New York: Macmillan. Eemeren F and Grootendorst R[1984] Speech acts in argumentative discussions Dordrecht: Foris. Eemeren F and Grootendorst R [1987] "Fallacies in pragma-dialectical perspective" Argumentation I: 283-301. Ennis R H [I974] "The believability of people" Educational Forum 39:347-54. Govier T [ed.] [1988] Selected issues in logic and communication Belmont CA: Wadsworth. Hamblin CH [1970] Fallacies London: Methuen. Hardwig J [1985] "Relying on experts" in Govier [1988] = "Epistemic dependence" J Phil 82.7:335-49. Locke J [1961] An essay concerning human understanding, ed. Yolton, London: Dent. Salmon M [1988J Introduction to logic and critical thinking. 2"d ed., San Diego, Ca.: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. Walton D [1989aJ "Reasoned use of expertise in argumentation" Argumentation 3: 59-73. Walton D [1989b]Informal Logic Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Willard C [1990] "Authority" Informal Logic 12.1: 11- Woods J and Walton D [1989] Fallacies. selected papers Dordrecht: Foris. Woods J and Walton D [1979a] "Argumentum ad verecundiam" ch2 of Woods and Walton [1989]. Woods J and Walton D [I 979b] "What type of argument is Ad verecundiam?" Chapter 14 of Woods and Walton [1989]. EDWIN COLEMAN PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT UNIVERSITY OF MELBOURNE PARKVILLE, AUSTRALIA 3052